Ludwig Wittgenstein
Part of a series on |
Ludwig Wittgenstein |
---|
Ludwig Josef Johann Wittgenstein (/ˈvɪtɡənʃtaɪn, -staɪn/ VIT-gən-s(h)tyne,[7] Austrian German: [ˈluːdvɪk ˈjoːsɛf ˈjoːhan ˈvɪtɡn̩ʃtaɪn]; 26 April 1889 – 29 April 1951) was an Austrian philosopher who worked primarily in logic, the philosophy of mathematics, the philosophy of mind, and the philosophy of language.[8]
From 1929 to 1947, Wittgenstein taught at the University of Cambridge.[8] Despite his position, only one book of his philosophy was published during his entire life: the 75-page Logisch-Philosophische Abhandlung (Logical-Philosophical Treatise, 1921), which appeared, together with an English translation, in 1922 under the Latin title Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. His only other published works were an article, "Some Remarks on Logical Form" (1929); a book review; and a children's dictionary.[a][b] His voluminous manuscripts were edited and published posthumously. The first and best-known of this posthumous series is the 1953 book Philosophical Investigations. A 1999 survey among American university and college teachers ranked the Investigations as the most important book of 20th-century philosophy, standing out as "the one crossover masterpiece in twentieth-century philosophy, appealing across diverse specializations and philosophical orientations".[9]
His philosophy is often divided into an early period, exemplified by the Tractatus, and a later period, articulated primarily in the Philosophical Investigations.[10] The "early Wittgenstein" was concerned with the logical relationship between propositions and the world, and he believed that by providing an account of the logic underlying this relationship, he had solved all philosophical problems. The "later Wittgenstein", however, rejected many of the assumptions of the Tractatus, arguing that the meaning of words is best understood as their use within a given language game.[11]
Born in Vienna into one of Europe's richest families, he inherited a fortune from his father in 1913. Before World War I, he "made a very generous financial bequest to a group of poets and artists chosen by Ludwig von Ficker, the editor of Der Brenner, from artists in need. These included Trakl as well as Rainer Maria Rilke and the architect Adolf Loos."[12] "In autumn 1916, as his sister reported, 'Ludwig made a donation of a million crowns ["equivalent to about $2,869,000 in 2016 dollars"] for the construction of a 30cm mortar.'"[13] Later, in a period of severe personal depression after World War I, he gave away his remaining fortune to his brothers and sisters.[14][15] Three of his four older brothers died by separate acts of suicide. Wittgenstein left academia several times: serving as an officer on the front line during World War I, where he was decorated a number of times for his courage; teaching in schools in remote Austrian villages, where he encountered controversy for using sometimes violent corporal punishment on both girls and boys (see, for example, the Haidbauer incident), especially during mathematics classes; working during World War II as a hospital porter in London; and working as a hospital laboratory technician at the Royal Victoria Infirmary in Newcastle upon Tyne.
Background
[edit]The Wittgensteins
[edit]According to a family tree prepared in Jerusalem after World War II, Wittgenstein's paternal great-great-grandfather was Moses Meier,[17] an Ashkenazi Jewish land agent who lived with his wife, Brendel Simon, in Bad Laasphe in the Principality of Wittgenstein, Westphalia.[18] In July 1808, Napoleon issued a decree that everyone, including Jews, must adopt an inheritable family surname, so Meier's son, also Moses, took the name of his employers, the Sayn-Wittgensteins, and became Moses Meier Wittgenstein.[19] His son, Hermann Christian Wittgenstein — who took the middle name "Christian" to distance himself from his Jewish background — married Fanny Figdor, also Jewish, who converted to Protestantism just before they married, and the couple founded a successful business trading in wool in Leipzig.[20] Ludwig's grandmother Fanny was a first cousin of the violinist Joseph Joachim.[21]
They had 11 children – among them Wittgenstein's father. Karl Otto Clemens Wittgenstein (1847–1913) became an industrial tycoon, and by the late 1880s was one of the richest men in Europe, with an effective monopoly on Austria's steel cartel.[16][22] Thanks to Karl, the Wittgensteins became the second wealthiest family in the Austro-Hungarian Empire, only the Rothschilds being wealthier.[22] Karl Wittgenstein was viewed as the Austrian equivalent of Andrew Carnegie, with whom he was friends, and was one of the wealthiest men in the world by the 1890s.[16] As a result of his decision in 1898 to invest substantially in the Netherlands and in Switzerland as well as overseas, particularly in the US, the family was to an extent shielded from the hyperinflation that hit Austria in 1922.[23] However, their wealth diminished due to post-1918 hyperinflation and subsequently during the Great Depression, although even as late as 1938 they owned 13 mansions in Vienna alone.[24]
Early life
[edit]Wittgenstein was ethnically Jewish.[25][26][27][28][29] His mother was Leopoldine Maria Josefa Kalmus, known among friends as "Poldi". Her father was a Bohemian Jew, and her mother was an Austrian-Slovene Catholic – she was Wittgenstein's only non-Jewish grandparent. Poldi was an aunt of the Nobel Prize laureate Friedrich Hayek on his maternal side. Wittgenstein was born at 8:30 PM on 26 April 1889 in the "Villa Wittgenstein" at what is today Neuwaldegger Straße 38 in the suburban parish Neuwaldegg next to Vienna.[30][31]
Karl and Poldi had nine children in all – four girls: Hermine, Margaret (Gretl), Helene, and a fourth daughter Dora who died as a baby; and five boys: Johannes (Hans), Kurt, Rudolf (Rudi), Paul – who became a concert pianist despite losing an arm in World War I – and Ludwig, who was the youngest of the family.[32]
The children were baptized as Catholics, received formal Catholic instruction, and were raised in an exceptionally intense environment.[33][page needed] The family was at the centre of Vienna's cultural life; Bruno Walter described the life at the Wittgensteins' palace as an "all-pervading atmosphere of humanity and culture."[34] Karl was a leading patron of the arts, commissioning works by Auguste Rodin and financing the city's exhibition hall and art gallery, the Secession Building. Gustav Klimt painted a portrait of Wittgenstein's sister Margaret for her wedding,[35] and Johannes Brahms and Gustav Mahler gave regular concerts in the family's numerous music rooms.[34][36]
Wittgenstein, who valued precision and discipline, never considered contemporary classical music acceptable. He said to his friend Drury in 1930:
Music came to a full stop with Brahms; and even in Brahms I can begin to hear the noise of machinery.[37]
Ludwig Wittgenstein himself had absolute pitch,[38] and his devotion to music remained vitally important to him throughout his life; he made frequent use of musical examples and metaphors in his philosophical writings, and he was unusually adept at whistling lengthy and detailed musical passages.[39] He also learnt to play the clarinet in his 30s.[40] A fragment of music (three bars), composed by Wittgenstein, was discovered in one of his 1931 notebooks, by Michael Nedo, director of the Wittgenstein Institute in Cambridge.[41]
Family temperament and the brothers' suicides
[edit]Ray Monk writes that Karl's aim was to turn his sons into captains of industry; they were not sent to school lest they acquire bad habits but were educated at home to prepare them for work in Karl's industrial empire.[42] Three of the five brothers later committed suicide.[43][44] Psychiatrist Michael Fitzgerald argues that Karl was a harsh perfectionist who lacked empathy, and that Wittgenstein's mother was anxious and insecure, unable to stand up to her husband.[45] Johannes Brahms said of the family, whom he visited regularly:
They seemed to act towards one another as if they were at court.[22]
The family appeared to have a strong streak of depression running through it. Anthony Gottlieb tells a story about Paul practising on one of the pianos in the Wittgensteins' main family mansion, when he suddenly shouted at Ludwig in the next room:
I cannot play when you are in the house, as I feel your skepticism seeping towards me from under the door![26]
The family palace housed seven grand pianos[46] and each of the siblings pursued music "with an enthusiasm that, at times, bordered on the pathological".[47] The eldest brother, Hans, was hailed as a musical prodigy. At the age of four, writes Alexander Waugh, Hans could identify the Doppler effect in a passing siren as a quarter-tone drop in pitch, and at five started crying "Wrong! Wrong!" when two brass bands in a carnival played the same tune in different keys. But he died in mysterious circumstances in May 1902, when he ran away to the US and disappeared from a boat in Chesapeake Bay, most likely having committed suicide.[48][49]
Two years later, aged 22 and studying chemistry at the Berlin Academy, the third eldest brother, Rudi, committed suicide in a Berlin bar. He had asked the pianist to play Thomas Koschat's "Verlassen, verlassen, verlassen bin ich" ("Forsaken, forsaken, forsaken am I"), before mixing himself a drink of milk and potassium cyanide. He had left several suicide notes, one to his parents that said he was grieving over the death of a friend, and another that referred to his "perverted disposition". It was reported at the time that he had sought advice from the Scientific-Humanitarian Committee, an organization that was campaigning against Paragraph 175 of the German Criminal Code, which prohibited homosexual sex. Ludwig himself was a closeted homosexual, who separated sexual intercourse from love, despising all forms of the former.[50] His father forbade the family from ever mentioning his name again.[51][52][53][26]
The second eldest brother, Kurt, an officer and company director, shot himself on 27 October 1918 just before the end of World War I, when the Austrian troops he was commanding refused to obey his orders and deserted en masse.[42] According to Gottlieb, Hermine had said Kurt seemed to carry "the germ of disgust for life within himself".[54] Later, Ludwig wrote:
I ought to have ... become a star in the sky. Instead of which I have remained stuck on earth.[55]
1903–1906: Realschule in Linz
[edit]Realschule in Linz
[edit]Wittgenstein was taught by private tutors at home until he was 14 years old. Subsequently, for three years, he attended a school. After the deaths of Hans and Rudi, Karl relented and allowed Paul and Ludwig to be sent to school. Waugh writes that it was too late for Wittgenstein to pass his exams for the more academic Gymnasium in Wiener Neustadt; having had no formal schooling, he failed his entrance exam and only barely managed after extra tutoring to pass the exam for the more technically oriented k.u.k. Realschule in Linz, a small state school with 300 pupils.[56][57][c] In 1903, when he was 14, he began his three years of formal schooling there, lodging nearby during the term with the family of Josef Strigl, a teacher at the local gymnasium, the family giving him the nickname Luki.[58][59]
On starting at the Realschule, Wittgenstein had been moved forward a year.[58] Historian Brigitte Hamann writes that he stood out from the other boys: he spoke an unusually pure form of High German with a stutter, dressed elegantly, and was sensitive and unsociable.[60] Monk writes that the other boys made fun of him, singing after him: "Wittgenstein wandelt wehmütig widriger Winde wegen Wienwärts"[40] ("Wittgenstein wanders wistfully Vienna-wards (in) worsening winds"). In his leaving certificate, he received a top mark (5) in religious studies; a 2 for conduct and English, 3 for French, geography, history, mathematics and physics, and 4 for German, chemistry, geometry and freehand drawing.[58] He had particular difficulty with spelling and failed his written German exam because of it. He wrote in 1931:
My bad spelling in youth, up to the age of about 18 or 19, is connected with the whole of the rest of my character (my weakness in study).[58]
Faith
[edit]Wittgenstein was baptized as an infant by a Catholic priest and received formal instruction in Catholic doctrine as a child, as was common at the time.[33][page needed] In an interview, his sister Gretl Stonborough-Wittgenstein says that their grandfather's "strong, severe, partly ascetic Christianity" was a strong influence on all the Wittgenstein children.[61] While he was at the Realschule, he decided he lacked religious faith and began reading Arthur Schopenhauer per Gretl's recommendation.[62] He nevertheless believed in the importance of the idea of confession. He wrote in his diaries about having made a major confession to his oldest sister, Hermine, while he was at the Realschule; Monk speculates that it may have been about his loss of faith. He also discussed it with Gretl, his other sister, who directed him to Schopenhauer's The World as Will and Representation.[62] As a teenager, Wittgenstein adopted Schopenhauer's epistemological idealism. However, after he studied the philosophy of mathematics, he abandoned epistemological idealism for Gottlob Frege's conceptual realism.[63] In later years, Wittgenstein was highly dismissive of Schopenhauer, describing him as an ultimately "shallow" thinker:
Schopenhauer is quite a crude mind ... Where real depth starts, his comes to an end.[64]
Wittgenstein's relationship with Christianity and with religion in general, for which he always professed a sincere and devoted sympathy, changed over time, much like his philosophical ideas.[65] In 1912, Wittgenstein wrote to Russell saying that Mozart and Beethoven were the actual sons of God.[66] However, Wittgenstein resisted formal religion, saying it was hard for him to "bend the knee",[67] though his grandfather's beliefs continued to influence Wittgenstein – as he said, "I cannot help seeing every problem from a religious point of view."[68] Wittgenstein referred to Augustine of Hippo in his Philosophical Investigations. Philosophically, Wittgenstein's thought shows alignment with religious discourse.[69] For example, he would become one of the century's fiercest critics of scientism.[70] Wittgenstein's religious belief emerged during his service for the Austrian army in World War I,[71] and he was a devoted reader of Dostoevsky's and Tolstoy's religious writings.[72] He viewed his wartime experiences as a trial in which he strove to conform to the will of God, and in a journal entry from 29 April 1915, he writes:
Perhaps the nearness of death will bring me the light of life. May God enlighten me. I am a worm, but through God I become a man. God be with me. Amen.[73]
Around this time, Wittgenstein wrote that "Christianity is indeed the only sure way to happiness", but he rejected the idea that religious belief was merely thinking that a certain doctrine was true.[74] From this time on, Wittgenstein viewed religious faith as a way of living and opposed rational argumentation or proofs for God. With age, a deepening personal spirituality led to several elucidations and clarifications, as he untangled language problems in religion—attacking, for example, the temptation to think of God's existence as a matter of scientific evidence.[75] In 1947, finding it more difficult to work, he wrote:
I have had a letter from an old friend in Austria, a priest. In it he says that he hopes my work will go well, if it should be God's will. Now that is all I want: if it should be God's will.[76]
In Culture and Value, Wittgenstein writes:
Is what I am doing [my work in philosophy] really worth the effort? Yes, but only if a light shines on it from above.
His close friend Norman Malcolm wrote:
Wittgenstein's mature life was strongly marked by religious thought and feeling. I am inclined to think that he was more deeply religious than are many people who correctly regard themselves as religious believers.[33][page needed]
Toward the end, Wittgenstein wrote:
Bach wrote on the title page of his Orgelbüchlein, 'To the glory of the most high God, and that my neighbour may be benefited thereby.' That is what I would have liked to say about my work.[76]
Influence of Otto Weininger
[edit]While a student at the Realschule, Wittgenstein was influenced by Austrian philosopher Otto Weininger's 1903 book Geschlecht und Charakter (Sex and Character). Weininger (1880–1903), who was Jewish, argued that the concepts of male and female exist only as Platonic forms, and that Jews tend to embody the Platonic femininity. Whereas men are basically rational, women operate only at the level of their emotions and sexual organs. Jews, Weininger argued, are similar, saturated with femininity, with no sense of right and wrong, and no soul. Weininger argues that man must choose between his masculine and feminine sides, consciousness and unconsciousness, platonic love and sexuality. Love and sexual desire stand in contradiction, and love between a woman and a man is therefore doomed to misery or immorality. The only life worth living is the spiritual one – to live as a woman or a Jew means one has no right to live at all; the choice is genius or death. Weininger committed suicide, shooting himself in 1903, shortly after publishing the book.[77] Wittgenstein, then 14, attended Weininger's funeral.[78] Many years later, as a professor at the University of Cambridge, Wittgenstein distributed copies of Weininger's book to his bemused academic colleagues. He said that Weininger's arguments were wrong, but that it was the way they were wrong that was interesting.[79] In a letter dated 23 August 1931, Wittgenstein wrote the following to G. E. Moore:
Dear Moore,
Thanks for your letter. I can quite imagine that you don't admire Weininger very much, what with that beastly translation and the fact that W. must feel very foreign to you. It is true that he is fantastic but he is great and fantastic. It isn't necessary or rather not possible to agree with him but the greatness lies in that with which we disagree. It is his enormous mistake which is great. I.e. roughly speaking if you just add a "~" to the whole book it says an important truth.[80]
In an unusual move, Wittgenstein took out a copy of Weininger's work on 1 June 1931 from the Special Order Books in the university library. He met Moore on 2 June, when he probably gave this copy to Moore.[80]
Jewish background and Hitler
[edit]Despite their and their forebears' Christianization, the Wittgensteins considered themselves Jewish. This was evident during the Nazi era, when Ludwig's sister was assured by an official that they wouldn't be considered as Jews under the racial laws. Indignant at the state's attempt to dictate her identity, she demanded papers certifying their Jewish lineage.[81]
In his own writings, Wittgenstein frequently referred to himself as Jewish, often in a self-deprecating manner. For instance, while criticizing himself for being a "reproductive" rather than a "productive" thinker, he attributed this to his Jewish sense of identity. He wrote: 'The saint is the only Jewish "genius". Even the greatest Jewish thinker is no more than talented. (Myself for instance).'[82]
There is much discussion around the extent to which Wittgenstein and his siblings, who were of 3/4 Jewish descent, saw themselves as Jews. The issue has arisen in particular regarding Wittgenstein's schooldays, because Adolf Hitler was, for a while, at the same school at the same time.[83] Laurence Goldstein argues that it is "overwhelmingly probable" that the boys met each other and that Hitler would have disliked Wittgenstein, a "stammering, precocious, precious, aristocratic upstart ..."; Strathern flatly states they never met.[84][85] Other commentators have dismissed as irresponsible and uninformed any suggestion that Wittgenstein's wealth and unusual personality might have fed Hitler's antisemitism, in part because there is no indication that Hitler would have seen Wittgenstein as Jewish.[86][87]
Wittgenstein and Hitler were born just six days apart, though Hitler had to re-sit his mathematics exam before being allowed into a higher class, while Wittgenstein was moved forward by one, so they ended up two grades apart at the Realschule.[56][d] Monk estimates that they were both at the school during the 1904–1905 school year, but says there is no evidence they had anything to do with each other.[60][89][e] Several commentators have argued that a school photograph of Hitler may show Wittgenstein in the lower left corner,[60][94][g]
While Wittgenstein would later claim that "[m]y thoughts are 100% Hebraic",[98] as Hans Sluga has argued, if so,
His was a self-doubting Judaism, which had always the possibility of collapsing into a destructive self-hatred (as it did in Weininger's case) but which also held an immense promise of innovation and genius.[99]
By Hebraic, he meant to include the Christian tradition, in contradistinction to the Greek tradition, holding that good and evil could not be reconciled.[100]
1906–1913: University
[edit]Engineering at Berlin and Manchester
[edit]He began his studies in mechanical engineering at the Technische Hochschule Berlin in Charlottenburg, Berlin, on 23 October 1906, lodging with the family of Professor Jolles. He attended for three semesters, and was awarded a diploma (Abgangzeugnis) on 5 May 1908.[101]
During his time at the Institute, Wittgenstein developed an interest in aeronautics.[102] He arrived at the Victoria University of Manchester in the spring of 1908 to study for a doctorate, full of plans for aeronautical projects, including designing and flying his own plane. He conducted research into the behaviour of kites in the upper atmosphere, experimenting at a meteorological observation site near Glossop in Derbyshire.[103] Specifically, the Royal Meteorological Society researched and investigated the ionization of the upper atmosphere, by suspending instruments on balloons or kites. At Glossop, Wittgenstein worked under Professor of Physics Sir Arthur Schuster.[104]
He also worked on the design of a propeller with small jet (Tip jet) engines on the end of its blades, something he patented in 1911, and that earned him a research studentship from the university in the autumn of 1908.[105] At the time, contemporary propeller designs were not advanced enough to actually put Wittgenstein's ideas into practice, and it would be years before a blade design that could support Wittgenstein's innovative design was created. Wittgenstein's design required air and gas to be forced along the propeller arms to combustion chambers on the end of each blade, where they were then compressed by the centrifugal force exerted by the revolving arms and ignited. Propellers of the time were typically wood, whereas modern blades are made from pressed steel laminates as separate halves, which are then welded together. This gives the blade a hollow interior and thereby creates an ideal pathway for the air and gas.[104]
Work on the jet-powered propeller proved frustrating for Wittgenstein, who had very little experience working with machinery.[106] Jim Bamber, a British engineer who was his friend and classmate at the time, reported that
when things went wrong, which often occurred, he would throw his arms around, stomp about, and swear volubly in German.[107]
According to William Eccles, another friend from that period, Wittgenstein then turned to more theoretical work, focusing on the design of the propeller – a problem that required relatively sophisticated mathematics.[106] It was at this time that he became interested in the foundations of mathematics, particularly after reading Bertrand Russell's The Principles of Mathematics (1903), and Gottlob Frege's The Foundations of Arithmetic, vol. 1 (1893) and vol. 2 (1903).[108] Wittgenstein's sister Hermine said he became obsessed with mathematics as a result, and was anyway losing interest in aeronautics.[109] He decided instead that he needed to study logic and the foundations of mathematics, describing himself as in a "constant, indescribable, almost pathological state of agitation."[109] In the summer of 1911 he visited Frege at the University of Jena to show him some philosophy of mathematics and logic he had written, and to ask whether it was worth pursuing.[110] He wrote:
I was shown into Frege's study. Frege was a small, neat man with a pointed beard who bounced around the room as he talked. He absolutely wiped the floor with me, and I felt very depressed; but at the end he said 'You must come again', so I cheered up. I had several discussions with him after that. Frege would never talk about anything but logic and mathematics, if I started on some other subject, he would say something polite and then plunge back into logic and mathematics.[111]
Arrival at Cambridge
[edit]Wittgenstein wanted to study with Frege, but Frege suggested he attend the University of Cambridge to study under Russell, so on 18 October 1911 Wittgenstein arrived unannounced at Russell's rooms in Trinity College.[112] Russell was having tea with C. K. Ogden, when, according to Russell,
an unknown German appeared, speaking very little English but refusing to speak German. He turned out to be a man who had learned engineering at Charlottenburg, but during this course had acquired, by himself, a passion for the philosophy of mathematics & has now come to Cambridge on purpose to hear me.[110]
He was soon not only attending Russell's lectures but dominating them. The lectures were poorly attended and Russell often found himself lecturing only to C. D. Broad, E. H. Neville, and H. T. J. Norton.[110] Wittgenstein started following him after lectures back to his rooms to discuss more philosophy, until it was time for the evening meal in Hall. Russell grew irritated; he wrote to his lover Lady Ottoline Morrell: "My German friend threatens to be an infliction."[113] Russell soon came to believe that Wittgenstein was a genius, especially after he had examined Wittgenstein's written work. He wrote in November 1911 that he had at first thought Wittgenstein might be a crank, but soon decided he was a genius:
Some of his early views made the decision difficult. He maintained, for example, at one time that all existential propositions are meaningless. This was in a lecture room, and I invited him to consider the proposition: 'There is no hippopotamus in this room at present.' When he refused to believe this, I looked under all the desks without finding one; but he remained unconvinced.[114]
Three months after Wittgenstein's arrival Russell told Morrell:
I love him & feel he will solve the problems I am too old to solve ... He is the young man one hopes for.[115]
Wittgenstein later told David Pinsent that Russell's encouragement had proven his salvation, and had ended nine years of loneliness and suffering, during which he had continually thought of suicide. In encouraging him to pursue philosophy and in justifying his inclination to abandon engineering, Russell had, quite literally, saved Wittgenstein's life.[115] The role-reversal between Bertrand Russell and Wittgenstein was soon such that Russell wrote in 1916 after Wittgenstein had criticized Russell's own work:
His [Wittgenstein's] criticism, tho' I don't think you realized it at the time, was an event of first-rate importance in my life, and affected everything I have done since. I saw that he was right, and I saw that I could not hope ever again to do fundamental work in philosophy.[116]
Cambridge Moral Sciences Club and Apostles
[edit]In 1912 Wittgenstein joined the Cambridge University Moral Sciences Club, an influential discussion group for philosophy dons and students, delivering his first paper there on 29 November that year, a four-minute talk defining philosophy as
all those primitive propositions which are assumed as true without proof by the various sciences.[117][118][119]
He dominated the society and for a time would stop attending in the early 1930s after complaints that he gave no one else a chance to speak.[120] The club became infamous within popular philosophy because of a meeting on 25 October 1946 at Richard Braithwaite's rooms in King's College, Cambridge, where Karl Popper, another Viennese philosopher, had been invited as the guest speaker. Popper's paper was "Are there philosophical problems?", in which he struck up a position against Wittgenstein's, contending that problems in philosophy are real, not just linguistic puzzles as Wittgenstein argued. Accounts vary as to what happened next, but Wittgenstein apparently started waving a hot poker, demanding that Popper give him an example of a moral rule. Popper offered one – "Not to threaten visiting speakers with pokers" – at which point Russell told Wittgenstein he had misunderstood and Wittgenstein left. Popper maintained that Wittgenstein "stormed out", but it had become accepted practice for him to leave early (because of his aforementioned ability to dominate discussion). It was the only time the philosophers, three of the most eminent in the 20th CE, were ever in the same room together.[121][122] The minutes record that the meeting was
charged to an unusual degree with a spirit of controversy.[123]
Cambridge Apostles
[edit]The economist John Maynard Keynes also invited him to join the Cambridge Apostles, an elite secret society formed in 1820, which both Bertrand Russell and G. E. Moore had joined as students, but Wittgenstein did not greatly enjoy it and attended only infrequently. Russell had been worried that Wittgenstein would not appreciate the group's raucous style of intellectual debate, its precious sense of humour, and the fact that the members were often in love with one another.[124][failed verification] He was admitted in 1912 but resigned almost immediately because he could not tolerate the style of discussion. Nevertheless, the Cambridge Apostles allowed Wittgenstein to participate in meetings again in the 1920s when he returned to Cambridge. Reportedly, Wittgenstein also had trouble tolerating the discussions in the Cambridge Moral Sciences Club.
Frustrations at Cambridge
[edit]Wittgenstein was quite vocal about his depression in his years at Cambridge and before he went to war; on many an occasion, he told Russell of his woes. His mental anguish seemed to stem from two sources: his work and his personal life. Wittgenstein made numerous remarks to Russell about the logic driving him mad.[125] Wittgenstein also stated to Russell that he "felt the curse of those who have half a talent".[126] He later expressed this same worry and told of being in mediocre spirits due to his lack of progress in his logical work.[127] Monk writes that Wittgenstein lived and breathed logic, and a temporary lack of inspiration plunged him into despair.[128] Wittgenstein told of his work in logic affecting his mental status in an extreme way. However, he also told Russell another story. Around Christmas, in 1913, he wrote:
how can I be a logician before I'm a human being? For the most important thing is coming to terms with myself![129]
He also told Russell on an occasion in Russell's rooms that he was worried about logic and his sins; also, once upon arriving in Russell's rooms one night, Wittgenstein announced to Russell that he would kill himself once he left.[130] Of things Wittgenstein personally told Russell, Ludwig's temperament was also recorded in the diary of David Pinsent. Pinsent wrote
I have to be frightfully careful and tolerant when he gets these sulky fits
and
I am afraid he is in an even more sensitive neurotic state just now than usual
when talking about Wittgenstein's emotional fluctuations.[131]
Sexual orientation and relationship with David Pinsent
[edit]Wittgenstein had romantic relations with both men and women. He is generally believed to have fallen in love with at least three men, and had a relationship with the latter two: David Hume Pinsent in 1912, Francis Skinner in 1930, and Ben Richards in the late 1940s.[132] He later claimed that, as a teenager in Vienna, he had had an affair with a woman.[133] Additionally, in the 1920s Wittgenstein fell in love with a young Swiss woman, Marguerite Respinger, sculpting a bust modelled on her and seriously considering marriage, albeit on condition that they would not have children; she decided that he was not right for her.[134]
Wittgenstein's relationship with David Pinsent occurred during an intellectually formative period and is well documented. Bertrand Russell introduced Wittgenstein to Pinsent in the summer of 1912. Pinsent was a mathematics undergraduate and a relation of David Hume, and Wittgenstein and he soon became very close.[135] The men worked together on experiments in the psychology laboratory about the role of rhythm in the appreciation of music, and Wittgenstein delivered a paper on the subject to the British Psychological Association in Cambridge in 1912. They also travelled together, including to Iceland in September 1912—the expenses paid by Wittgenstein, including first class travel, the hiring of a private train, and new clothes and spending money for Pinsent. In addition to Iceland, Wittgenstein and Pinsent travelled to Norway in 1913. In determining their destination, Wittgenstein and Pinsent visited a tourist office in search of a location that would fulfil the following criteria: a small village located on a fjord, a location away from tourists, and a peaceful destination to allow them to study logic and law.[136] Choosing Øystese, Wittgenstein and Pinsent arrived in the small village on 4 September 1913. During a vacation lasting almost three weeks, Wittgenstein was able to work vigorously on his studies. The immense progress on logic during their stay led Wittgenstein to express to Pinsent his notion of leaving Cambridge and returning to Norway to continue his work on logic.[137] Pinsent's diaries provide valuable insights into Wittgenstein's personality: sensitive, nervous, and attuned to the tiniest slight or change in mood from Pinsent.[138][139] Pinsent also writes of Wittgenstein being "absolutely sulky and snappish" at times, as well.[131] In his diaries Pinsent wrote about shopping for furniture with Wittgenstein in Cambridge when the latter was given rooms in Trinity. Most of what they found in the stores was not minimalist enough for Wittgenstein's aesthetics:
I went and helped him interview a lot of furniture at various shops ... It was rather amusing: He is terribly fastidious and we led the shopman a frightful dance, Vittgenstein [sic] ejaculating "No – Beastly!" to 90 percent of what he shewed us![140]
He wrote in May 1912 that Wittgenstein had just begun to study the history of philosophy:
He expresses the most naive surprise that all the philosophers he once worshipped in ignorance are after all stupid and dishonest and make disgusting mistakes![140]
The last time they saw each other was on 8 October 1913 at Lordswood House in Birmingham, then residence of the Pinsent family:
I got up at 6:15 to see Ludwig off. He had to go very early—back to Cambridge—as he has lots to do there. I saw him off from the house in a taxi at 7:00—to catch a 7:30 AM train from New Street Station. It was sad parting from him.[139]
Wittgenstein left to live in Norway.
1913–1920: World War I and the Tractatus
[edit]Work on Logik
[edit]Karl Wittgenstein died on 20 January 1913, and after receiving his inheritance Wittgenstein became one of the wealthiest men in Europe.[141] He donated some of his money, at first anonymously, to Austrian artists and writers, including Rainer Maria Rilke and Georg Trakl. Trakl requested to meet his benefactor but in 1914 when Wittgenstein went to visit, Trakl had killed himself. Wittgenstein came to feel that he could not get to the heart of his most fundamental questions while surrounded by other academics, and so in 1913, he retreated to the village of Skjolden in Norway, where he rented the second floor of a house for the winter.[142] He later saw this as one of the most productive periods of his life, writing Logik (Notes on Logic), the predecessor of much of the Tractatus.[112]
While in Norway, Wittgenstein learned Norwegian to converse with the local villagers, and Danish to read the works of the Danish philosopher Søren Kierkegaard.[143] He adored the "quiet seriousness" of the landscape but even Skjolden became too busy for him. He soon designed a small wooden house which was erected on a remote rock overlooking the Eidsvatnet Lake just outside the village. The place was called "Østerrike" (Austria) by locals. He lived there during various periods until the 1930s, and substantial parts of his works were written there. (The house was broken up in 1958 to be rebuilt in the village. A local foundation collected donations and bought it in 2014; it was dismantled again and re-erected at its original location; the inauguration took place on 20 June 2019 with international attendance.)[142]
It was during this time that Wittgenstein began addressing what he considered to be a central issue in Notes on Logic, a general decision procedure for determining the truth value of logical propositions that would stem from a single primitive proposition. He became convinced during this time that
All the propositions of logic are generalizations of tautologies and all generalizations of tautologies are generalizations of logic. There are no other logical propositions.[144]
Based on this, Wittgenstein argued that propositions of logic express their truth or falsehood in the sign itself, and one need not know anything about the constituent parts of the proposition to determine it true or false. Rather, one simply needs to identify the statement as a tautology (true), a contradiction (false), or neither. The problem lay in forming a primitive proposition that encompassed this and would act as the basis for all of logic. As he stated in correspondence with Russell in late 1913,
The big question now is, how must a system of signs be constituted in order to make every tautology recognizable as such IN ONE AND THE SAME WAY? This is the fundamental problem of logic![127]
The importance Wittgenstein placed upon this fundamental problem was so great that he believed if he did not solve it, he had no reason or right to live.[145] Despite this apparent life-or-death importance, Wittgenstein had given up on this primitive proposition by the time of the writing of the Tractatus. The Tractatus does not offer any general process for identifying propositions as tautologies; in a simpler manner,
Every tautology itself shows that it is a tautology.[146]
This shift to understanding tautologies through mere identification or recognition occurred in 1914 when Moore was called on by Wittgenstein to assist him in dictating his notes.
At Wittgenstein's insistence, Moore, who was now a Cambridge don, visited him in Norway in April 1914, reluctantly because Wittgenstein exhausted him. David Edmonds and John Eidinow write that Wittgenstein regarded Moore, an internationally known philosopher, as an example of how far someone could get in life with "absolutely no intelligence whatever."[147] In Norway it was clear that Moore was expected to act as Wittgenstein's secretary, taking down his notes, with Wittgenstein falling into a rage when Moore got something wrong.[148]
Brian McGuinness notes that a letter from Wittgenstein to Moore of 7 May 1914 indicates that he had intended to submit an essay he referred to as "Logik" as the dissertation required for his completion of a bachelor's degree. [149][150] McGuinness asserts that the essay is unlikely to be identical with “Notes on Logic” but suggests it as at least summarised in "Notes dictated to G. E. Moore in Norway” (published in Appendix II of Notebooks 1914-1916)[151] and that 'much speaks' for the supposition that it was indeed these notes that Wittgenstein had intended to submit.[149] According to the relevant regulations, however, such a dissertation had to contain a preface and notes in which the student stated the sources he had relied on, and the extent to which he had done so, qualities lacking in Wittgenstein's essay, Moore, though himself Secretary of the relevant Moral Sciences degrees committee, showed the essay to Walter Morley Fletcher – perhaps, McGuinness suggests, "for an impartial opinion from an outsider" – and "been told that it could not possibly pass for a dissertation" and wrote to Wittgenstein accordingly,[149]
Wittgenstein was furious, writing to Moore:
If I am not worth your making an exception for me even in some STUPID details then I may as well go to Hell directly; and if I am worth it and you don't do it then – by God – you might go there.[152]
Moore was apparently distraught; writing in his diary that he felt sick and could not get the letter out of his head.[153] Wittgenstein wrote to Moore In July of that year conceding the he had "probably no sufficient reason to write to you as I did"[149][150] but the two did not speak again until 1929.[148]
Military service
[edit]On the outbreak of World War I, Wittgenstein immediately volunteered for the Austro-Hungarian Army, despite being eligible for a medical exemption.[154][155] He served first on a ship and then in an artillery workshop "several miles from the action".[154] He was wounded in an accidental explosion, and hospitalised to Kraków.[154] In March 1916, he was posted to a fighting unit on the front line of the Russian front, as part of the Austrian 7th Army, where his unit was involved in some of the heaviest fighting, defending against the Brusilov Offensive.[156] Wittgenstein directed the fire of his own artillery from an observation post in no-man's land against Allied troops—one of the most dangerous jobs since he was targeted by enemy fire.[155] He was decorated with the Military Merit Medal with Swords on the Ribbon, and was commended by the army for "exceptionally courageous behaviour, calmness, sang-froid, and heroism" that "won the total admiration of the troops".[157] In January 1917, he was sent as a member of a howitzer regiment to the Russian front, where he won several more medals for bravery including the Silver Medal for Valour, First Class.[158] In 1918, he was promoted to lieutenant and sent to the Italian front as part of an artillery regiment. For his part in the final Austrian offensive of June 1918, he was recommended for the Gold Medal for Valour, one of the highest honours in the Austrian army, but was instead awarded the Band of the Military Service Medal with Swords—it being decided that this particular action, although extraordinarily brave, had been insufficiently consequential to merit the highest honour.[159]
Throughout the war, he kept notebooks in which he frequently wrote philosophical reflections alongside personal remarks, including his contempt for the character of the other soldiers.[160] His notebooks also attest to his philosophical and spiritual reflections, and it was during this time that he experienced a kind of religious awakening.[71] In his entry from 11 June 1915, Wittgenstein states that
The meaning of life, i.e. the meaning of the world, we can call God.
And connect with this the comparison of God to a father.
To pray is to think about the meaning of life.[161]
and on 8 July that
To believe in God means to understand the meaning of life.
To believe in God means to see that the facts of the world are not the end of the matter.
To believe in God means to see that life has a meaning [ ... ]
When my conscience upsets my equilibrium, then I am not in agreement with Something. But what is this? Is it the world?
Certainly it is correct to say: Conscience is the voice of God.[162]
He discovered Leo Tolstoy's 1896 The Gospel in Brief at a bookshop in Tarnów, and carried it everywhere, recommending it to anyone in distress, to the point where he became known to his fellow soldiers as "the man with the gospels".[163][164]
The extent to which The Gospel in Brief influenced Wittgenstein can be seen in the Tractatus, in the unique way both books number their sentences.[165] In 1916 Wittgenstein read Dostoevsky's The Brothers Karamazov so often that he knew whole passages of it by heart, particularly the speeches of the elder Zosima, who represented for him a powerful Christian ideal, a holy man "who could see directly into the souls of other people".[72][166]
Iain King has suggested that Wittgenstein's writing changed substantially in 1916 when he started confronting much greater dangers during frontline fighting.[167] Russell said he returned from the war a changed man, one with a deeply mystical and ascetic attitude.[168]
Completion of the Tractatus
[edit]In the summer of 1918, Wittgenstein took military leave and went to stay in one of his family's Vienna summer houses, Neuwaldegg. It was there in August 1918 that he completed the Tractatus, which he submitted with the title Der Satz (German: proposition, sentence, phrase, set, but also "leap") to the publishers Jahoda and Siegel.[169]
A series of events around this time left him deeply upset. On 13 August, his uncle Paul died. On 25 October, he learned that Jahoda and Siegel had decided not to publish the Tractatus, and on 27 October, his brother Kurt killed himself, the third of his brothers to commit suicide. It was around this time he received a letter from David Pinsent's mother to say that Pinsent had been killed in a plane crash on 8 May.[170][171] Wittgenstein was distraught to the point of being suicidal. He was sent back to the Italian front after his leave and, as a result of the defeat of the Austrian army, he was captured by Allied forces on 3 November in Trentino. He subsequently spent nine months in an Italian prisoner of war camp.
He returned to his family in Vienna on 25 August 1919, by all accounts physically and mentally spent. He apparently talked incessantly about suicide, terrifying his sisters and brother Paul. He decided to do two things: to enroll in a teacher training college as an elementary school teacher, and to get rid of his fortune. In 1914, it had been providing him with an income of 300,000 Kronen a year, but by 1919 was worth a great deal more, with a sizable portfolio of investments in the United States and the Netherlands. He divided it among his siblings, except for Margarete, insisting that it not be held in trust for him. His family saw him as ill and acquiesced.[169]
1920–1928: Teaching, the Tractatus, Haus Wittgenstein
[edit]Teacher training in Vienna
[edit]In September 1919 he enrolled in the Lehrerbildungsanstalt (teacher training college) in the Kundmanngasse in Vienna. His sister Hermine said that Wittgenstein working as an elementary teacher was like using a precision instrument to open crates, but the family decided not to interfere.[172] Thomas Bernhard, more critically, wrote of this period in Wittgenstein's life: "the multi-millionaire as a village schoolmaster is surely a piece of perversity."[173]
Teaching posts in Austria
[edit]In the summer of 1920, Wittgenstein worked as a gardener for a monastery. At first, he applied under a false name, for a teaching post at Reichenau, and was awarded the job, but he declined it when his identity was discovered. As a teacher, he wished to no longer be recognized as a member of the Wittgenstein family. In response, his brother Paul wrote:
It is out of the question, really completely out of the question, that anybody bearing our name and whose elegant and gentle upbringing can be seen a thousand paces off, would not be identified as a member of our family ... That one can neither simulate nor dissimulate anything including a refined education I need hardly tell you.[174]
In 1920, Wittgenstein was given his first job as a primary school teacher in Trattenbach, under his real name, in a remote village of a few hundred people. His first letters describe it as beautiful, but in October 1921, he wrote to Russell: "I am still at Trattenbach, surrounded, as ever, by odiousness and baseness. I know that human beings on the average are not worth much anywhere, but here they are much more good-for-nothing and irresponsible than elsewhere."[175] He was soon the object of gossip among the villagers, who found him eccentric at best. He did not get on well with the other teachers; when he found his lodgings too noisy, he made a bed for himself in the school kitchen. He was an enthusiastic teacher, offering late-night extra tuition to several of the students, something that did not endear him to the parents, though some of them came to adore him; his sister Hermine occasionally watched him teach and said the students "literally crawled over each other in their desire to be chosen for answers or demonstrations."[176]
To the less able, it seems that he became something of a tyrant. The first two hours of each day were devoted to mathematics, hours that Monk writes some of the pupils recalled years later with horror.[177] They reported that he caned the boys and boxed their ears, and also that he pulled the girls' hair;[178] this was not unusual at the time for boys, but for the villagers he went too far in doing it to the girls too; girls were not expected to understand algebra, much less have their ears boxed over it. The corporal punishment apart, Monk writes that he quickly became a village legend, shouting "Krautsalat!" ("coleslaw" – i.e. shredded cabbage) when the headmaster played the piano, and "Nonsense!" when a priest was answering children's questions.[179]
Publication of the Tractatus
[edit]While Wittgenstein was living in isolation in rural Austria, the Tractatus was published to considerable interest, first in German in 1921 as Logisch-Philosophische Abhandlung, part of Wilhelm Ostwald's journal Annalen der Naturphilosophie, though Wittgenstein was not happy with the result and called it a pirate edition. Russell had agreed to write an introduction to explain why it was important because it was otherwise unlikely to have been published: it was difficult if not impossible to understand, and Wittgenstein was unknown in philosophy.[180] In a letter to Russell, Wittgenstein wrote "The main point is the theory of what can be expressed (gesagt) by prop[osition]s – i.e. by language – (and, which comes to the same thing, what can be thought) and what can not be expressed by pro[position]s, but only shown (gezeigt); which, I believe, is the cardinal problem of philosophy."[181] But Wittgenstein was not happy with Russell's help. He had lost faith in Russell, finding him glib and his philosophy mechanistic, and felt he had fundamentally misunderstood the Tractatus.[182]
The whole modern conception of the world is founded on the illusion that the so-called laws of nature are the explanations of natural phenomena. Thus people today stop at the laws of nature, treating them as something inviolable, just as God and Fate were treated in past ages. And in fact both were right and both wrong; though the view of the ancients is clearer insofar as they have an acknowledged terminus, while the modern system tries to make it look as if everything were explained.
— Wittgenstein, Tractatus, 6.371-2
An English translation was prepared in Cambridge by Frank Ramsey, a mathematics undergraduate at King's commissioned by C. K. Ogden. It was Moore who suggested Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus for the title, an allusion to Baruch Spinoza's Tractatus Theologico-Politicus. Initially, there were difficulties in finding a publisher for the English edition too, because Wittgenstein was insisting it appear without Russell's introduction; Cambridge University Press turned it down for that reason. Finally in 1922 an agreement was reached with Wittgenstein that Kegan Paul would print a bilingual edition with Russell's introduction and the Ramsey-Ogden translation.[183] This is the translation that was approved by Wittgenstein, but it is problematic in a number of ways. Wittgenstein's English was poor at the time, and Ramsey was a teenager who had only recently learned German, so philosophers often prefer to use a 1961 translation by David Pears and Brian McGuinness.[h]
An aim of the Tractatus is to reveal the relationship between language and the world: what can be said about it, and what can only be shown. Wittgenstein argues that the logical structure of language provides the limits of meaning. The limits of language, for Wittgenstein, are the limits of philosophy. Much of philosophy involves attempts to say the unsayable: "What we can say at all can be said clearly," he argues. Anything beyond that – religion, ethics, aesthetics, the mystical – cannot be discussed. They are not in themselves nonsensical, but any statement about them must be.[185] He wrote in the preface: "The book will, therefore, draw a limit to thinking, or rather – not to thinking, but to the expression of thoughts; for, in order to draw a limit to thinking we should have to be able to think both sides of this limit (we should therefore have to be able to think what cannot be thought)."[186]
The book is 75 pages long – "As to the shortness of the book, I am awfully sorry for it ... If you were to squeeze me like a lemon you would get nothing more out of me," he told Ogden – and presents seven numbered propositions (1–7), with various sub-levels (1, 1.1, 1.11):[187]
- Die Welt ist alles, was der Fall ist.
- The world is everything that is the case.[188]
- Was der Fall ist, die Tatsache, ist das Bestehen von Sachverhalten.
- What is the case, the fact, is the existence of atomic facts.
- Das logische Bild der Tatsachen ist der Gedanke.
- The logical picture of the facts is the thought.
- Der Gedanke ist der sinnvolle Satz.
- The thought is the significant proposition.
- Der Satz ist eine Wahrheitsfunktion der Elementarsätze.
- Propositions are truth-functions of elementary propositions.
- Die allgemeine Form der Wahrheitsfunktion ist: . Dies ist die allgemeine Form des Satzes.
- The general form of a truth-function is: . This is the general form of proposition.
- Wovon man nicht sprechen kann, darüber muß man schweigen.
- Whereof one cannot speak, thereof one must be silent.
Visit from Frank Ramsey, Puchberg
[edit]In September 1922 he moved to a secondary school in a nearby village, Hassbach, but considered the people there just as bad – "These people are not human at all but loathsome worms," he wrote to a friend – and he left after a month. In November he began work at another primary school, this time in Puchberg in the Schneeberg mountains. There, he told Russell, the villagers were "one-quarter animal and three-quarters human."
Frank P. Ramsey visited him on 17 September 1923 to discuss the Tractatus; he had agreed to write a review of it for Mind.[189] He reported in a letter home that Wittgenstein was living frugally in one tiny whitewashed room that only had space for a bed, a washstand, a small table, and one small hard chair. Ramsey shared an evening meal with him of coarse bread, butter, and cocoa. Wittgenstein's school hours were eight to twelve or one, and he had afternoons free.[190] After Ramsey returned to Cambridge a long campaign began among Wittgenstein's friends to persuade him to return to Cambridge and away from what they saw as a hostile environment for him. He was accepting no help even from his family.[191] Ramsey wrote to John Maynard Keynes:
[Wittgenstein's family] are very rich and extremely anxious to give him money or do anything for him in any way, and he rejects all their advances; even Christmas presents or presents of invalid's food, when he is ill, he sends back. And this is not because they aren't on good terms but because he won't have any money he hasn't earned ... It is an awful pity.[191]
Teaching continues, Otterthal; Standard Austrian German; Haidbauer incident
[edit]He moved schools again in September 1924, this time to Otterthal, near Trattenbach; the socialist headmaster, Josef Putre, was someone Wittgenstein had become friends with while at Trattenbach. While he was there, he wrote a 42-page pronunciation and spelling dictionary for the children, Wörterbuch für Volksschulen, published in Vienna in 1926 by Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky, the only book of his apart from the Tractatus that was published in his lifetime.[183] A first edition sold in 2005 for £75,000.[192] In 2020, an English version entitled Word Book translated by art historian Bettina Funcke and illustrated by artist / publisher Paul Chan was released.[193]
The Wörterbuch für Volksschulen is remarkable for its pluricentric conceptualization, decades before such a linguistic approach existed. In Wittgenstein's preface to the Wörterbuch, which was withheld at the publisher's request but which survives in a 1925 typescript, Wittgenstein takes a clear stance for a Standard Austrian German, which he aimed to document for elementary pupils in the text. Wittgenstein states (translated from German) that
The dictionary should include only words, but all such words, that are known to Austrian elementary students. Therefore it excludes many a good German word unusual in Austria.[194]
Wittgenstein is through his school dictionary one of the earliest proponents of a German with more than one standard variety.[194] This is especially noteworthy in the German language context, in which expert debates over the status and relevance of standard varieties are so common that some speak of a One Standard German Axiom in that field today. Wittgenstein was taking a stance for multiple standards, against such an axiom, long before these debates ensued. An incident occurred in April 1926 and became known as Der Vorfall Haidbauer (the Haidbauer incident). Josef Haidbauer was an 11-year-old pupil whose father had died and whose mother worked as a local maid. He was a slow learner, and one day Wittgenstein hit him two or three times on the head, causing him to collapse. Wittgenstein carried him to the headmaster's office, then quickly left the school, bumping into a parent, Herr Piribauer, on the way out. Piribauer had been sent for by the children when they saw Haidbauer collapse; Wittgenstein had previously pulled Piribauer's daughter, Hermine, so hard by the ears that her ears had bled.[195] Piribauer said that when he met Wittgenstein in the hall that day:
I called him all the names under the sun. I told him he wasn't a teacher, he was an animal-trainer! And that I was going to fetch the police right away![196]
Piribauer tried to have Wittgenstein arrested, but the village's police station was empty, and when he tried again the next day he was told Wittgenstein had disappeared. On 28 April 1926, Wittgenstein handed in his resignation to Wilhelm Kundt, a local school inspector, who tried to persuade him to stay; however, Wittgenstein was adamant that his days as a schoolteacher were over.[196] Proceedings were initiated in May, and the judge ordered a psychiatric report; in August 1926 a letter to Wittgenstein from a friend, Ludwig Hänsel, indicates that hearings were ongoing, but nothing is known about the case after that. Alexander Waugh writes that Wittgenstein's family and their money may have had a hand in covering things up. Waugh writes that Haidbauer died shortly afterwards of haemophilia; Monk says he died when he was 14 of leukaemia.[197][198] Ten years later, in 1936, as part of a series of "confessions" he engaged in that year, Wittgenstein appeared without warning at the village saying he wanted to confess personally and ask for pardon from the children he had hit. He visited at least four of the children, including Hermine Piribauer, who apparently replied only with a "Ja, ja," though other former students were more hospitable. Monk writes that the purpose of these confessions was not
to hurt his pride, as a form of punishment; it was to dismantle it – to remove a barrier, as it were, that stood in the way of honest and decent thought.
Of the apologies, Wittgenstein wrote,
This brought me into more settled waters... and to greater seriousness.[199]
The Vienna Circle
[edit]The Tractatus was now the subject of much debate among philosophers, and Wittgenstein was a figure of increasing international fame. In particular, a discussion group of philosophers, scientists, and mathematicians, known as the Vienna Circle, had developed purportedly as a result of the inspiration they had been given by reading the Tractatus.[191] While it is commonly assumed that Wittgenstein was a part of the Vienna Circle, in reality, this was not the case. German philosopher Oswald Hanfling writes bluntly: "Wittgenstein was never a member of the Circle, though he was in Vienna during much of the time. Yet his influence on the Circle's thought was at least as important as that of any of its members."[200]
Philosopher A. C. Grayling, however, contends that while certain superficial similarities between Wittgenstein's early philosophy and logical positivism led its members to study the Tractatus in detail and to arrange discussions with him, Wittgenstein's influence on the Circle was rather limited. The fundamental philosophical views of Circle had been established before they met Wittgenstein and had their origins in the British empiricists, Ernst Mach, and the logic of Frege and Russell. Whatever influence Wittgenstein did have on the Circle was largely limited to Moritz Schlick and Friedrich Waismann and, even in these cases, had little lasting effect on their positivism. Grayling states that "it is no longer possible to think of the Tractatus as having inspired a philosophical movement, as most earlier commentators claimed."[201]
From 1926, Wittgenstein took part in many discussions with the members of the Vienna Circle. During these discussions, it soon became evident that Wittgenstein held a different attitude towards philosophy from the members of the Circle. For example, during meetings of the Vienna Circle, he would express his disagreement with the group's misreading of his work by turning his back to them and reading poetry aloud.[202] In his autobiography, Rudolf Carnap describes Wittgenstein as the thinker who most inspired him. However, he also wrote that "there was a striking difference between Wittgenstein's attitude toward philosophical problems and that of Schlick and myself. Our attitude toward philosophical problems was not very different from that which scientists have toward their problems." As for Wittgenstein:
His point of view and his attitude toward people and problems, even theoretical problems, were much more similar to those of a creative artist than to those of a scientist; one might almost say, similar to those of a religious prophet or a seer.... When finally, sometimes after a prolonged arduous effort, his answers came forth, his statement stood before us like a newly created piece of art or a divine revelation ... the impression he made on us was as if insight came to him as through divine inspiration, so that we could not help feeling that any sober rational comment or analysis of it would be a profanation.[203]
Haus Wittgenstein
[edit]I am not interested in erecting a building, but in [...] presenting to myself the foundations of all possible buildings.
— Wittgenstein[204]
In 1926 Wittgenstein was again working as a gardener for a number of months, this time at the monastery of Hütteldorf, where he had also inquired about becoming a monk. His sister, Margaret, invited him to help with the design of her new townhouse in Vienna's Kundmanngasse. Wittgenstein, his friend Paul Engelmann, and a team of architects developed a spare modernist house. In particular, Wittgenstein focused on the windows, doors, and radiators, demanding that every detail be exactly as he specified. When the house was nearly finished Wittgenstein had an entire ceiling raised 30 mm so that the room had the exact proportions he wanted. Monk writes that "This is not so marginal as it may at first appear, for it is precisely these details that lend what is otherwise a rather plain, even ugly house its distinctive beauty."[205]
It took him a year to design the door handles and another to design the radiators. Each window was covered by a metal screen that weighed 150 kilograms (330 lb), moved by a pulley Wittgenstein designed. Bernhard Leitner, author of The Architecture of Ludwig Wittgenstein, said there is barely anything comparable in the history of interior design: "It is as ingenious as it is expensive. A metal curtain that could be lowered into the floor."[205]
The house was finished by December 1928 and the family gathered there at Christmas to celebrate its completion. Wittgenstein's sister Hermine wrote: "Even though I admired the house very much. ... It seemed indeed to be much more a dwelling for the gods."[204] Wittgenstein said "the house I built for Gretl is the product of a decidedly sensitive ear and good manners, and expression of great understanding... But primordial life, wild life striving to erupt into the open – that is lacking."[206] Monk comments that the same might be said of the technically excellent, but austere, terracotta sculpture Wittgenstein had modelled of Marguerite Respinger in 1926, and that, as Russell first noticed, this "wild life striving to be in the open" was precisely the substance of Wittgenstein's philosophical work.[206]
1929–1941: Fellowship at Cambridge
[edit]PhD and fellowship
[edit]According to Feigl (as reported by Monk), upon attending a conference in Vienna by mathematician L. E. J. Brouwer, Wittgenstein remained quite impressed, taking into consideration the possibility of a "return to Philosophy". At the urging of Ramsey and others, Wittgenstein returned to Cambridge in 1929. Keynes wrote in a letter to his wife: "Well, God has arrived. I met him on the 5.15 train."[207] Despite this fame, he could not initially work at Cambridge as he had failed to obtain a degree, so he applied as an advanced undergraduate. Russell noted that his previous residency was sufficient to fulfil eligibility requirements for a PhD, and urged him to offer the Tractatus as his thesis.[208] It was examined in 1929 by Russell and Moore; at the end of the thesis defence, Wittgenstein clapped the two examiners on the shoulder and said, '"Don't worry, I know you'll never understand it."[209] Moore wrote in the examiner's report: "I myself consider that this is a work of genius; but, even if I am completely mistaken and it is nothing of the sort, it is well above the standard required for the Ph.D. degree."[210] Wittgenstein was appointed as a lecturer and was made a fellow of Trinity College.
Anschluss
[edit]From 1936 to 1937, Wittgenstein lived again in Norway,[211] where he worked on the Philosophical Investigations. In the winter of 1936/7, he delivered a series of "confessions" to close friends, most of them about minor infractions like white lies, in an effort to cleanse himself. In 1938, he travelled to Ireland to visit Maurice O'Connor Drury, a friend who became a psychiatrist, and considered such training himself, with the intention of abandoning philosophy for it. The visit to Ireland was at the same time a response to the invitation of the then Irish Taoiseach, Éamon de Valera, himself a former mathematics teacher. De Valera hoped Wittgenstein's presence would contribute to the Dublin Institute for Advanced Studies which he was soon to set up.[212]
While he was in Ireland in March 1938, Germany annexed Austria in the Anschluss; the Viennese Wittgenstein was now a Jew under the 1935 Nuremberg racial laws, because three of his grandparents had been born as Jews. He would also, in July, become by law a citizen of the enlarged Germany.[5]
The Nuremberg Laws classified people as Jews (Volljuden) if they had three or four Jewish grandparents, and as mixed blood (Mischling) if they had one or two. It meant, among other things, that the Wittgensteins were restricted in whom they could marry or have sex with, and where they could work.[213]
After the Anschluss, his brother Paul left almost immediately for England, and later the US. The Nazis discovered his relationship with Hilde Schania, a brewer's daughter with whom he had had two children but whom he had never married, though he did later. Because she was not Jewish, he was served with a summons for Rassenschande (racial defilement). He told no one he was leaving the country, except for Hilde who agreed to follow him. He left so suddenly and quietly that for a time people believed he was the fourth Wittgenstein brother to have committed suicide.[214]
Wittgenstein began to investigate acquiring British or Irish citizenship with the help of Keynes, and apparently had to confess to his friends in England that he had earlier misrepresented himself to them as having just one Jewish grandparent, when in fact he had three.[215]
A few days before the invasion of Poland, Hitler personally granted Mischling status to the Wittgenstein siblings. In 1939 there were 2,100 applications for this, and Hitler granted only 12.[216] Anthony Gottlieb writes that the pretext was that their paternal grandfather had been the bastard son of a German prince, which allowed the Reichsbank to claim foreign currency, stocks and 1700 kg of gold held in Switzerland by a Wittgenstein family trust. Gretl, an American citizen by marriage, started the negotiations over the racial status of their grandfather, and the family's large foreign currency reserves were used as a bargaining tool. Paul had escaped to Switzerland and then the US in July 1938, and disagreed with the negotiations, leading to a permanent split between the siblings. After the war, when Paul was performing in Vienna, he did not visit Hermine who was dying there, and he had no further contact with Ludwig or Gretl.[26]
Professor of philosophy
[edit]After G. E. Moore resigned the chair in philosophy in 1939, Wittgenstein was elected. He was naturalised as a British subject shortly after on 12 April 1939.[217] In July 1939 he travelled to Vienna to assist Gretl and his other sisters, visiting Berlin for one day to meet an official of the Reichsbank. After this, he travelled to New York to persuade Paul, whose agreement was required, to back the scheme. The required Befreiung was granted in August 1939. The unknown amount signed over to the Nazis by the Wittgenstein family, a week or so before the outbreak of war, included amongst many other assets 1,700 kg of gold.[218]
Norman Malcolm, at the time a post-graduate research fellow at Cambridge, describes his first impressions of Wittgenstein in 1938:
At a meeting of the Moral Science Club, after the paper for the evening was read and the discussion started, someone began to stammer a remark. He had extreme difficulty in expressing himself and his words were unintelligible to me. I whispered to my neighbour, 'Who's that?': he replied, 'Wittgenstein'. I was astonished because I had expected the famous author of the Tractatus to be an elderly man, whereas this man looked young – perhaps about 35. (His actual age was 49.) His face was lean and brown, his profile was aquiline and strikingly beautiful, his head was covered with a curly mass of brown hair. I observed the respectful attention that everyone in the room paid to him. After this unsuccessful beginning, he did not speak for a time but was obviously struggling with his thoughts. His look was concentrated, he made striking gestures with his hands as if he was discoursing ... Whether lecturing or conversing privately, Wittgenstein always spoke emphatically and with a distinctive intonation. He spoke excellent English, with the accent of an educated Englishman, although occasional Germanisms would appear in his constructions. His voice was resonant ... His words came out, not fluently, but with great force. Anyone who heard him say anything knew that this was a singular person. His face was remarkably mobile and expressive when he talked. His eyes were deep and often fierce in their expression. His whole personality was commanding, even imperial.[219]
Describing Wittgenstein's lecture programme, Malcolm continues:
It is hardly correct to speak of these meetings as 'lectures', although this is what Wittgenstein called them. For one thing, he was carrying on original research in these meetings ... Often the meetings consisted mainly of dialogue. Sometimes, however, when he was trying to draw a thought out of himself, he would prohibit, with a peremptory motion of the hand, any questions or remarks. There were frequent and prolonged periods of silence, with only an occasional mutter from Wittgenstein, and the stillest attention from the others. During these silences, Wittgenstein was extremely tense and active. His gaze was concentrated; his face was alive; his hands made arresting movements; his expression was stern. One knew that one was in the presence of extreme seriousness, absorption, and force of intellect ... Wittgenstein was a frightening person at these classes.[220]
After work, the philosopher would often relax by watching Westerns, where he preferred to sit at the very front of the cinema, or reading detective stories especially the ones written by Norbert Davis.[221][222] Norman Malcolm wrote that Wittgenstein would rush to the cinema when class ended.[223]
By this time, Wittgenstein's view on the foundations of mathematics had changed considerably. In his early 20s, Wittgenstein had thought logic could provide a solid foundation, and he had even considered updating Russell and Whitehead's Principia Mathematica. Now he denied there were any mathematical facts to be discovered. He gave a series of lectures on mathematics, discussing this and other topics, documented in a book, with some of his lectures and discussions between him and several students, including the young Alan Turing, who described Wittgenstein as "a very peculiar man". The two had many discussions about the relationship between computational logic and everyday notions of truth.[224][225][226]
Wittgenstein's lectures from this period have also been discussed by another of his students, the Greek philosopher and educator Helle Lambridis. Wittgenstein's teachings in the years 1940–1941 were used in the mid-1950s by Lambridis to write a long text in the form of an imagined dialogue with him, where she begins to develop her own ideas about resemblance in relation to language, elementary concepts and basic-level mental images. Initially, only a part of it was published in 1963 in the German education theory review Club Voltaire, but the entire imagined dialogue with Wittgenstein was published after Lambridis's death by her archive holder, the Academy of Athens, in 2004.[227][228]
1941–1947: Guy's Hospital and Royal Victoria Infirmary
[edit]Monk writes that Wittgenstein found it intolerable that a war (World War II) was going on and he was teaching philosophy. He grew angry when any of his students wanted to become professional philosophers.[i]
In September 1941, he asked John Ryle, the brother of the philosopher Gilbert Ryle, if he could get a manual job at Guy's Hospital in London. John Ryle was professor of medicine at Cambridge and had been involved in helping Guy's prepare for the Blitz. Wittgenstein told Ryle he would die slowly if left at Cambridge, and he would rather die quickly. He started working at Guy's shortly afterwards as a dispensary porter, delivering drugs from the pharmacy to the wards where he apparently advised the patients not to take them.[229] In the new year of 1942, Ryle took Wittgenstein to his home in Sussex to meet his wife who had been determined to meet him. His son recorded the weekend in his diary;
Wink is awful strange [sic] – not a very good english speaker, keeps on saying 'I mean' and 'its "tolerable"' meaning intolerable.[230]
The hospital staff were not told he was one of the world's most famous philosophers, though some of the medical staff did recognize him – at least one had attended Moral Sciences Club meetings – but they were discreet. "Good God, don't tell anybody who I am!" Wittgenstein begged one of them.[231] Some of them nevertheless called him Professor Wittgenstein, and he was allowed to dine with the doctors. He wrote on 1 April 1942: "I no longer feel any hope for the future of my life. It is as though I had before me nothing more than a long stretch of living death. I cannot imagine any future for me other than a ghastly one. Friendless and joyless."[229] It was at this time that Wittgenstein had an operation at Guy's to remove a gallstone that had troubled him for some years.[232]
He had developed a friendship with Keith Kirk, a working-class teenage friend of Francis Skinner, the mathematics undergraduate he had had a relationship with until Skinner's death in 1941 from polio. Skinner had given up academia, thanks at least in part to Wittgenstein's influence, and had been working as a mechanic in 1939, with Kirk as his apprentice. Kirk and Wittgenstein struck up a friendship, with Wittgenstein giving him lessons in physics to help him pass a City and Guilds exam. During his period of loneliness at Guy's he wrote in his diary: "For ten days I've heard nothing more from K, even though I pressed him a week ago for news. I think that he has perhaps broken with me. A tragic thought!"[233] Kirk had in fact got married, and they never saw one another again.[234]
While Wittgenstein was at Guy's he met Basil Reeve, a young doctor with an interest in philosophy, who, with R. T. Grant,[235] was studying the effect of wound shock[236] (a state associative to hypovolaemia[237]) on air-raid casualties. When the Blitz ended there were fewer casualties to study. In November 1942, Grant and Reeve moved to the Royal Victoria Infirmary, Newcastle upon Tyne, to study road traffic and industrial casualties. Grant offered Wittgenstein a position as a laboratory assistant at a wage of £4 per week, and he lived in Newcastle (at 28 Brandling Park, Jesmond[235]) from 29 April 1943 until February 1944.[238] While there he worked [239][240] and associated socially with Erasmus Barlow,[240] a great-grandson of Charles Darwin.[241]
In the summer of 1946, Wittgenstein thought often of leaving Cambridge and resigning his position as Chair. Wittgenstein grew further dismayed at the state of philosophy, particularly about articles published in the journal Mind. It was around this time that Wittgenstein fell in love with Ben Richards (who was a medical student), writing in his diary, "The only thing that my love for B. has done for me is this: it has driven the other small worries associated with my position and my work into the background." On 30 September, Wittgenstein wrote about Cambridge after his return from Swansea, "Everything about the place repels me. The stiffness, the artificiality, the self-satisfaction of the people. The university atmosphere nauseates me."[242]
Wittgenstein had only maintained contact with Fouracre, from Guy's hospital, who had joined the army in 1943 after his marriage, only returning in 1947. Wittgenstein maintained frequent correspondence with Fouracre during his time away displaying a desire for Fouracre to return home urgently from the war.[242]
In May 1947, Wittgenstein addressed a group of Oxford philosophers for the first time at the Jowett Society. The discussion was on the validity of Descartes' Cogito ergo sum, where Wittgenstein ignored the question and applied his own philosophical method. Harold Arthur Prichard who attended the event was not pleased with Wittgenstein's methods;
Wittgenstein: If a man says to me, looking at the sky, 'I think it will rain, therefore I exist', I do not understand him.
Prichard: That's all very fine; what we want to know is: is the cogito valid or not?[243]
1947–1951: Final years
[edit]Death is not an event in life: We do not live to experience death. If we take eternity to mean not infinite temporal duration but timelessness, then eternal life belongs to those who live in the present. Our life has no end in the way in which our visual field has no limits.
— Wittgenstein, Tractatus, 6.431
Wittgenstein resigned from the professorship at Cambridge in 1947 to concentrate on his writing, and in 1947 and 1948 travelled to Ireland, staying at Ross's Hotel in Dublin and at a farmhouse in Redcross, County Wicklow, where he began the manuscript MS 137, volume R.[244] Seeking solitude he moved to a holiday cottage in Rosroe overlooking Killary Harbour, Connemara owned by Drury's brother.[245]
He also accepted an invitation from Norman Malcolm, then a professor at Cornell University, to stay with him and his wife for several months in Ithaca, New York. He made the trip in April 1949, although he told Malcolm he was too unwell to do philosophical work: "I haven't done any work since the beginning of March & I haven't had the strength of even trying to do any." A doctor in Dublin had diagnosed anaemia and prescribed iron and liver pills. The details of Wittgenstein's stay in the US are recounted in Norman Malcolm's Ludwig Wittgenstein: A Memoir.[246] During his summer in the US, Wittgenstein began his epistemological discussions, in particular his engagement with philosophical scepticism, that would eventually become the final fragments On Certainty.
He returned to London, where he was diagnosed with an inoperable prostate cancer, which had spread to his bone marrow. He spent the next two months in Vienna, where his sister Hermine died on 11 February 1950; he went to see her every day, but she was hardly able to speak or recognize him. "Great loss for me and all of us," he wrote. "Greater than I would have thought." He moved frequently after Hermine's death, staying with various friends: to Cambridge in April 1950, where he stayed with G.H. von Wright; to London to stay with Rush Rhees; then to Oxford to see Elizabeth Anscombe, writing to Norman Malcolm that he was doing hardly any philosophy. He went to Norway in August with Ben Richards, then returned to Cambridge, where on 27 November he moved into Storey's End at 76 Storey's Way, the home of his doctor, Edward Bevan, and his wife Joan; he had told them he did not want to die in a hospital, so they said he could spend his last days in their home instead. Joan at first was afraid of Wittgenstein, but they soon became good friends.[244][247]
By the beginning of 1951, it was clear that he had little time left. He wrote a new will in Oxford on 29 January, naming Rhees as his executor, and Anscombe and von Wright as his literary administrators, and wrote to Norman Malcolm that month to say, "My mind's completely dead. This isn't a complaint, for I don't really suffer from it. I know that life must have an end once and that mental life can cease before the rest does."[247] In February, he returned to the Bevans' home to work on MS 175 and MS 176. These and other manuscripts were later published as Remarks on Colour and On Certainty.[244] He wrote to Malcolm on 16 April, 13 days before his death:
An extraordinary thing happened to me. About a month ago I suddenly found myself in the right frame of mind for doing philosophy. I had been absolutely certain that I'd never again be able to do it. It's the first time after more than 2 years that the curtain in my brain has gone up. – Of course, so far I've only worked for about 5 weeks & it may be all over by tomorrow; but it bucks me up a lot now.[248]
Death
[edit]Wittgenstein began work on his final manuscript, MS 177, on 25 April 1951. It was his 62nd birthday on 26 April. He went for a walk the next afternoon, and wrote his last entry that day, 27 April. That evening, he became very ill; when his doctor told him he might live only a few days, he reportedly replied, "Good!". Joan stayed with him throughout that night, and just before losing consciousness for the last time on 28 April, he told her: "Tell them I've had a wonderful life." Norman Malcolm describes this as a "strangely moving utterance".[248]
Four of Wittgenstein's former students arrived at his bedside – Ben Richards, Elizabeth Anscombe, Yorick Smythies, and Maurice O'Connor Drury. Anscombe and Smythies were Catholics; and, at the latter's request, a Dominican friar, Father Conrad Pepler, also attended. (Wittgenstein had asked for a "priest who was not a philosopher" and had met with Pepler several times before his death.)[249] They were at first unsure what Wittgenstein would have wanted, but then remembered he had said he hoped his Catholic friends would pray for him, so they did, and he was pronounced dead shortly afterwards.
Wittgenstein was given a Catholic burial at Ascension Parish Burial Ground in Cambridge.[250] Drury later said he had been troubled ever since about whether that was the right thing to do.[251] In 2015 the ledger gravestone was refurbished by the British Wittgenstein Society.[252]
On his religious views, Wittgenstein was said to be greatly interested in Catholicism, and was sympathetic to it, but did not consider himself to be a Catholic. According to Norman Malcolm, Wittgenstein saw Catholicism more as a way of life than as a set of beliefs he held, considering that he did not accept any religious faith.[j]
Wittgenstein has no goal to either support or reject religion; his only interest is to keep discussions, whether religious or not, clear. — T. Labron (2006)[254]
Wittgenstein was said by some commentators to be agnostic, in a qualified sense.[k][256]
I won't say 'See you tomorrow' because that would be like predicting the future, and I'm pretty sure I can't do that.
— Wittgenstein (1949)[257]
1953: Publication of the Philosophical Investigations
[edit]The Blue Book, a set of notes dictated to his class at Cambridge in 1933–1934, contains the seeds of Wittgenstein's later thoughts on language and is widely read as a turning point in his philosophy of language.
Philosophical Investigations was published in two parts in 1953. Most of Part I was ready for printing in 1946, but Wittgenstein withdrew the manuscript from his publisher. The shorter Part II was added by his editors, Elizabeth Anscombe and Rush Rhees. Wittgenstein asks the reader to think of language as a multiplicity of language games within which parts of language develop and function. He argues that the bewitchments of philosophical problems arise from philosophers' misguided attempts to consider the meaning of words independently of their context, usage, and grammar — what he called "language gone on holiday".[258]
According to Wittgenstein, philosophical problems arise when language is forced from its proper home into a metaphysical environment, where all the familiar and necessary landmarks and contextual clues are removed. He describes this metaphysical environment as like being on frictionless ice: where the conditions are apparently perfect for a philosophically and logically perfect language, all philosophical problems can be solved without the muddying effects of everyday contexts; but where, precisely because of the lack of friction, language can in fact do no work at all.[259] Wittgenstein argues that philosophers must leave the frictionless ice and return to the "rough ground" of ordinary language in use. Much of the Investigations consists of examples of how the first false steps can be avoided, so that philosophical problems are dissolved, rather than solved: "The clarity we are aiming at is indeed complete clarity. But this simply means that the philosophical problems should completely disappear."[260]
Other posthumous publications
[edit]Wittgenstein's archive of unpublished papers included 83 manuscripts, 46 typescripts and 11 dictations, amounting to an estimated 20,000 pages. Choosing among repeated drafts, revisions, corrections, and loose notes, editorial work has found nearly one-third of the total suitable for print.[261] An Internet facility hosted by the University of Bergen allows access to images of almost all the material and to search the available transcriptions.[262] In 2011, two new boxes of Wittgenstein papers, thought to have been lost during the Second World War, were found.[263][264]
What became the Philosophical Investigations was already close to completion in 1951. Wittgenstein's three literary executors prioritized it, both because of its intrinsic importance and because he had explicitly intended publication. The book was published in 1953.
At least three other works were more or less finished. Two were already "bulky typescripts", the Philosophical Remarks and Philosophical Grammar. Literary (co-)executor G. H. von Wright stated, "They are virtually completed works. But Wittgenstein did not publish them."[265] The third was Remarks on Colour. "He wrote i.a. a fair amount on colour concepts, and this material he did excerpt and polish, reducing it to a small compass."[266]
Legacy
[edit]Assessment
[edit]Bertrand Russell described Wittgenstein as "perhaps the most perfect example I have ever known of genius as traditionally conceived; passionate, profound, intense, and dominating."[124]
In 1999, a survey among American university and college teachers ranked the Investigations as the most important book of 20th-century philosophy, standing out as "the one crossover masterpiece in twentieth-century philosophy, appealing across diverse specializations and philosophical orientations."[267][268] The Investigations also ranked 54th on a list of most influential twentieth-century works in cognitive science prepared by the University of Minnesota's Center for Cognitive Sciences.[269]
Duncan J. Richter of the Virginia Military Institute, writing for the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, has described Wittgenstein as "one of the most influential philosophers of the twentieth century, and regarded by some as the most important since Immanuel Kant."[270] Peter Hacker argues that Wittgenstein's influence on 20th-century analytical philosophy can be attributed to his early influence on the Vienna Circle and later influence on the Oxford "ordinary language" school and Cambridge philosophers.[271]
He is considered by some to be one of the greatest philosophers of the modern era.[272] But despite its deep influence on analytical philosophy, Wittgenstein's work did not always gain a positive reception. Argentine-Canadian philosopher Mario Bunge considers that "Wittgenstein is popular because he is trivial."[273] In Bunge's opinion, Wittgenstein's philosophy is trivial because it deals with unimportant problems and ignores science.[274] According to Bunge, Wittgenstein's philosophy of language is shallow because it ignores scientific linguistics.[275] Bunge also considers Wittgenstein's philosophy of mind to be speculative because it is not informed by the scientific research performed in psychology.[276]
Scholarly interpretation
[edit]There are many diverging interpretations of Wittgenstein's thought. In the words of his friend and colleague Georg Henrik von Wright:
He was of the opinion ... that his ideas were generally misunderstood and distorted even by those who professed to be his disciples. He doubted that he would be better understood in the future. He once said that he felt as though he were writing for people who would think in a quite different way, breathe a different air of life, from that of present-day men.[277]
Since Wittgenstein's death, scholarly interpretations of his philosophy have differed. Scholars have differed on the continuity between the so-called early Wittgenstein and the so-called late(r) Wittgenstein (that is, the difference between his views expressed in the Tractatus and those in Philosophical Investigations), with some seeing the two as starkly disparate and others stressing the gradual transition between the two works through analysis of Wittgenstein's unpublished papers (the Nachlass).[278]
The New Wittgenstein
[edit]One significant debate in Wittgenstein scholarship concerns the work of interpreters who are referred to under the banner of The New Wittgenstein school such as Cora Diamond, Alice Crary, and James F. Conant. While the Tractatus, particularly in its conclusion, seems paradoxical and self-undermining, New Wittgenstein scholars advance a "therapeutic" understanding of Wittgenstein's work – "an understanding of Wittgenstein as aspiring, not to advance metaphysical theories, but rather to help us work ourselves out of confusions we become entangled in when philosophizing."[279] To support this goal, the New Wittgenstein scholars propose a reading of the Tractatus as "plain nonsense" – arguing it does not attempt to convey a substantive philosophical project but instead simply tries to push the reader to abandon philosophical speculation. The therapeutic approach traces its roots to the philosophical work of John Wisdom[280] and the review of The Blue Book written by Oets Kolk Bouwsma.[278][281]
The therapeutic approach is not without critics: Hans-Johann Glock argues that the "plain nonsense" reading of the Tractatus "is at odds with the external evidence, writings and conversations in which Wittgenstein states that the Tractatus is committed to the idea of ineffable insight."[278]
Hans Sluga and Rupert Read have advocated a "post-therapeutic" or "liberatory" interpretation of Wittgenstein.[282][283][284]
Bertrand Russell
[edit]In October 1944, Wittgenstein returned to Cambridge around the same time as did Russell, who had been living in the United States for several years. Russell returned to Cambridge after a backlash in the US to his writings on morals and religion. Wittgenstein said of Russell's works to Drury:
Russell's books should be bound in two colours...those dealing with mathematical logic in red – and all students of philosophy should read them; those dealing with ethics and politics in blue – and no one should be allowed to read them.[285]
Russell made similar disparaging comments about Wittgenstein's later work:
I have not found in Wittgenstein's Philosophical Investigations anything that seemed to me interesting and I do not understand why a whole school finds important wisdom in its pages. Psychologically this is surprising. The earlier Wittgenstein, whom I knew intimately, was a man addicted to passionately intense thinking, profoundly aware of difficult problems of which I, like him, felt the importance, and possessed (or at least so I thought) of true philosophical genius. The later Wittgenstein, on the contrary, seems to have grown tired of serious thinking and to have invented a doctrine which would make such an activity unnecessary. I do not for one moment believe that the doctrine which has these lazy consequences is true. I realize, however, that I have an overpoweringly strong bias against it, for, if it is true, philosophy is, at best, a slight help to lexicographers, and at worst, an idle tea-table amusement.[286]
Saul Kripke
[edit]Saul Kripke's 1982 book Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language contends that the central argument of Wittgenstein's Philosophical Investigations is a devastating rule-following paradox that undermines the possibility of ever following rules in our use of language. Kripke writes that this paradox is "the most radical and original sceptical problem that philosophy has seen to date."[287]
Kripke's book generated a large secondary literature, divided between those who find his sceptical problem interesting and perceptive, and others, such as John McDowell, Stanley Cavell, Gordon Baker, Peter Hacker, Colin McGinn,[288] and Peter Winch who argue that his scepticism of meaning is a pseudo-problem that stems from a confused, selective reading of Wittgenstein. Kripke's position has, however, recently been defended against these and other attacks by the Cambridge philosopher Martin Kusch (2006).
Works
[edit]A collection of Ludwig Wittgenstein's manuscripts is held by Trinity College, Cambridge.
- Logisch-Philosophische Abhandlung, Annalen der Naturphilosophie, 14 (1921)
- Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus [TLP], translated by C. K. Ogden (1922)
- "Some Remarks on Logical Form" (1929), Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, Volume 9, Issue 1, 15 July 1929, pp. 162–171.
- Philosophische Untersuchungen (1953)
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1958) [1953]. Philosophical Investigations. Translated by G. E. M. Anscombe. New York: MacMillan. Retrieved 14 November 2023.
- Bemerkungen über die Grundlagen der Mathematik, ed. by G. H. von Wright, R. Rhees, and G. E. M. Anscombe (1956), a selection of his work on the philosophy of logic and mathematics between 1937 and 1944.
- Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics, translated by G. E. M. Anscombe, rev. ed. (1978)
- Bemerkungen über die Philosophie der Psychologie, ed. G. E. M. Anscombe and G. H. von Wright (1980)
- Remarks on the Philosophy of Psychology, Vols. 1 and 2, translated by G. E. M. Anscombe, ed. G. E. M. Anscombe and G. H. von Wright (1980), a selection of which makes up Zettel.
- Blue and Brown Books (1958), notes dictated in English to Cambridge students in 1933–1935.
- Philosophische Bemerkungen, ed. by Rush Rhees (1964)
- Lectures and Conversations on Aesthetics, Psychology, and Religious Belief, ed. by Y. Smythies, R. Rhees, and J. Taylor (1967)
- Remarks on Frazer's Golden Bough, ed. by R. Rhees (1967)
- Philosophical Remarks (1975)
- Philosophical Grammar (1978)
- Bemerkungen über die Farben, ed. by G. E. M. Anscombe (1977)
- Remarks on Colour (1991), remarks on Goethe's Theory of Colours.
- On Certainty, collection of aphorisms discussing the relation between knowledge and certainty, extremely influential in the philosophy of action (1969)
- Culture and Value: A Selection from the Posthumous Remains, collection of personal remarks about cultural issues, such as religion and music, as well as a critique of Søren Kierkegaard's philosophy (1984, revised edition 1998).
- Zettel, collection of Wittgenstein's thoughts in fragmentary "diary entry" format as with On Certainty and Culture and Value (1967).
- Notebooks, 1914–1916, translated by G. E. M. Anscombe. Oxford: Basil Blackwell; New York: Harper & Row, Publishers, 1961.
- Private Notebooks, 1914–1916, translated by Marjorie Perloff. New York: Liveright Publishing Corporation, 2022.
- The Big Typescript: TS 213 German-English Scholars' Edition. Wiley-Blackwell, 2012. Unpublished typescript from 1933, written between the Tractatus and Philosophical Investigations
- Movements of Thought: Ludwig Wittgenstein's Diary, 1930–1932 and 1936–1937. New York: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2023.
- Public and Private Occasions. New York: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2003.
- Gibson, Arthur and O'Mahony, Niamh, eds. (2020), Ludwig Wittgenstein: Dictating Philosophy. New York: Springer Publishing. Previously unpublished manuscripts dictated to Francis Skinner.
- Works online
- Wittgenstein: Gesamtbriefwechsel/Complete Correspondence. Innsbrucker Electronic Edition: Ludwig Wittgenstein: Gesamtbriefwechsel/Complete Correspondence contains Wittgenstein's collected correspondence, edited under the auspices of the Brenner-Archiv's Research Institute (University of Innsbruck). Editors (first edition): Monika Seekircher, Brian McGuinness and Anton Unterkircher. Editors (second edition): Anna Coda, Gabriel Citron, Barbara Halder, Allan Janik, Ulrich Lobis, Kerstin Mayr, Brian McGuinness, Michael Schorner, Monika Seekircher and Joseph Wang.
- Wittgensteins Nachlass. The Bergen Electronic Edition: The collection includes all of Wittgenstein's unpublished manuscripts, typescripts, dictations, and most of his notebooks. The Nachlass was catalogued by G. H. von Wright in his "The Wittgenstein Papers", first published in 1969, and later updated and included as a chapter with the same title in his book Wittgenstein, published by Blackwell (and by the University of Minnesota Press in the U.S.) in 1982.
- Review of P. Coffey's Science of Logic Archived 30 April 2006 at the Wayback Machine (1913): a polemical book review, written in 1912 for the March 1913 issue of The Cambridge Review when Wittgenstein was an undergraduate studying with Russell. The review is the earliest public record of Wittgenstein's philosophical views.
- Nachlass online
- Works by Ludwig Wittgenstein at Project Gutenberg
- Bemerkungen über die Farben (Remarks on Colour)
- "Some Remarks on Logical Form"
- Cambridge (1932–3) lecture notes
- "On Certainty". Archived from the original on 10 December 2005. Retrieved 20 November 2008.
See also
[edit]- Definitions of philosophy
- International Wittgenstein Symposium
- Paul Horwich's views on the Antiphilosophy of Wittgenstein
Footnotes
[edit]- ^ For his publications during his lifetime, see Monk (2005), p. 5.
- ^ For the number of words published in his lifetime, see Stern (2010).
- ^ The successor institution to the Realschule in Linz is Bundesrealgymnasium Linz Fadingerstraße.
- ^ Hitler started at the school on 17 September 1900, repeated the first year in 1901, and left in the autumn of 1905.[88]
- ^ Brigitte Hamann argues in Hitler's Vienna that Hitler was bound to have laid eyes on Wittgenstein, because the latter was so conspicuous, though she told Focus magazine that they were in different classes, and she agrees with Monk that they would have had nothing to do with one another.[90][91]
- ^ Blum's material was on display in an exhibition (Open House, March 11 – May 2, 2004) at the OK Centrum für Gegenwartskunst, Linz,[92] and at the Galerija Nova, Zagreb in 2006.[93]
- ^ Hamann says the photograph stems from 1900 or 1901, before Wittgenstein's time.[91] The German Federal Archives says the image was taken "circa 1901"; it identifies the class as 1B and the teacher as Oskar Langer.[95] The archive gives the date as circa 1901, but wrongly calls the place the Realschule in Leonding, near Linz. Hitler attended primary school in Leonding, but from September 1901 went to the Realschule in Linz itself.[96] Christoph Haidacher and Richard Schober write that Langer taught at the school from 1884 until 1901.[97]
- ^ For example, Ramsey translated "Sachverhalt" and "Sachlage" as "atomic fact" and "state of affairs" respectively. But Wittgenstein discusses non-existent "Sachverhalten", and there cannot be a non-existent fact. Pears and McGuinness made a number of changes, including translating "Sachverhalt" as "state of affairs" and "Sachlage" as situation. The new translation is often preferred, but some philosophers use the original, in part because Wittgenstein approved it, and because it avoids the idiomatic English of Pears & McGuinness.[184]
- For a discussion about the relative merits of the translations, see Morris, Michael Rowland (2008). "Introduction". Routledge philosophy guidebook to Wittgenstein and the Tractatus. Taylor & Francis. and Nelson, John O. (April 1999). "Is the Pears-McGuinness translation of the Tractatus really superior to Ogden's and Ramsey's?". Philosophical Investigations. 22 (2): 165–175. doi:10.1111/1467-9205.00092.
- See the three versions (Wittgenstein's German, published 1921; Ramsey-Ogden's translation, published 1922; and the Pears & McGuinness translation, published 1961) side by side: "Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus". (Side-by-side-by-side edition, version 0.42. University of Massachusetts. 5 January 2015. Archived from the original on 9 August 2016.
- ^ For his desire that his students not pursue philosophy, see Malcolm (1958), p. 28.
- ^ I believe that Wittgenstein was prepared by his own character and experience to comprehend the idea of a judging and redeeming God. But any cosmological conception of a Deity, derived from the notions of cause or of infinity, would be repugnant to him. He was impatient with 'proofs' of the existence of God, and with attempts to give religion a rational foundation. ... I do not wish to give the impression that Wittgenstein accepted any religious faith – he certainly did not – or that he was a religious person. But I think that there was in him, in some sense, the possibility of religion. I believe that he looked on religion as a 'form of life' (to use an expression from the Investigations) in which he did not participate, but with which he was sympathetic and which greatly interested him. Those who did participate he respected – although here as elsewhere he had contempt for insincerity. I suspect that he regarded religious belief as based on qualities of character and will that he himself did not possess. Of Smythies and Anscombe, both of whom had become Roman Catholics, he once said to me: 'I could not possibly bring myself to believe all the things that they believe.' I think that in this remark he was not disparaging their belief. It was rather an observation about his own capacity. — N. Malcolm & G.H. von Wright (2001)[253]
- ^ "Was Wittgenstein religious? If we call him an agnostic, this must not be understood in the sense of the familiar polemical agnosticism that concentrates and prides itself, on the argument that man could never know about these matters. The idea of a God in the sense of the Bible, the image of God as the creator of the world, hardly ever engaged Wittgenstein's attention ..., but the notion of a last judgement was of profound concern to him." — Engelmann (W. Child, 2011)[255]
References
[edit]- ^ GLOCK, HANS-JOHANN (2004). "Was Wittgenstein an Analytic Philosopher?". Metaphilosophy. 35 (4): 419–444. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9973.2004.00329.x. ISSN 0026-1068. JSTOR 24439710.
- ^ Rodych, Victor. "Wittgenstein's Philosophy of Mathematics". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2018 ed.).
- ^ P. M. S. Hacker, Wittgenstein's Place in Twentieth-Century Analytic Philosophy (1996), pp. 77 and 138.
- ^ Nuno Venturinha, The Textual Genesis of Wittgenstein's Philosophical Investigations, Routledge, 2013, p. 39.
- ^ a b "documentArchiv.de – Verordnung über die deutsche Staatsangehörigkeit im Lande Österreich (3 July 1938)". documentarchiv.de. Retrieved 10 November 2022.
- ^ Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1958) [1953]. Philosophical Investigations. Translated by G. E. M. Anscombe. New York: MacMillan. Retrieved 14 November 2023.
- ^ "Wittgenstein". Random House Webster's Unabridged Dictionary. Retrieved 6 April 2020.
- ^ a b Dennett, Daniel (29 March 1999). "Ludwig Wittgenstein: Philosopher". Time. Archived from the original on 16 October 2007.
- ^ Lackey, Douglas P. (1999). "What Are the Modern Classics? The Baruch Poll of Great Philosophy in the Twentieth Century". The Philosophical Forum. 30 (4): 329–346. doi:10.1111/0031-806X.00022. ISSN 1467-9191.
- ^ His mentor Bertrand Russell was likely the first to coin this distinction in Wittgenstein's work.
- ^ Proops, Ian (2001). "The New Wittgenstein: A Critique" (PDF). European Journal of Philosophy. 9 (3): 375–404. doi:10.1111/1468-0378.00142. Retrieved 16 February 2018.
- ^ Wittgenstein, Ludwig, Private Notebooks: 1914–1916 (edited and translated by Marjorie Perloff), New York: Liveright Publishing Corporation, 2022, p. 79.
- ^ Klagge, James C. (2021), Wittgenstein's Artillery: Philosophy as Poetry. Cambridge, Massachusetts; London, England: The MIT Press, p. 3.
- ^ "Ludwig Wittgenstein or the Philosophy of Austere Lines". Goethe Institute. Archived from the original on 2 March 2011.
When his father died in 1913 ... Ludwig inherited a considerable fortune.... Then, after World War I, in which he fought as a volunteer in the Austro-Hungarian army, he gave away his entire [remaining] fortune to his brothers and sisters and, plagued by depression, sought refuge in Lower Austria, where he worked as a primary school teacher.
- ^ Duffy, Bruce (13 November 1988). "The Do-It-Yourself Life of Ludwig Wittgenstein". The New York Times.
- ^ a b c Bramann, Jorn K.; Moran, John (1979). "Karl Wittgenstein, Business Tycoon and Art Patron". Frostburg State University. 15: 106–124. doi:10.1017/S0067237800012686. S2CID 144157990. Archived from the original on 25 June 2018. Retrieved 2 September 2010.
- ^ Preston, John. "Wittgenstein Family History – Ludwig Wittgenstein: A Chronology of his Life and Work". www.wittgensteinchronology.com. Archived from the original on 6 July 2018. Retrieved 6 July 2018.
- ^ See Schloss Wittgenstein. Various sources spell Meier's name, Maier and Meyer.
- ^ Bartley 1994, pp. 199–200.
- ^ Monk 1990, pp. 4–5.
- ^ Monk 1990, p. 5.
- ^ a b c Edmonds & Eidinow 2001, p. 63.
- ^ Monk 1990, p. 7.
- ^ Edmonds & Eidinow 2001, p. 102.
- ^ Chatterjee, Ranjit (2005). Wittgenstein and Judaism: A Triumph of Concealment. Peter Lang. p. 178. ISBN 978-0-8204-7256-0.
- ^ a b c d Gottlieb, Anthony (9 April 2009). "A Nervous Splendor". The New Yorker.
- ^ "Wittgenstein, Leopoldine (Schenker Documents Online)". mt.ccnmtl.columbia.edu. Archived from the original on 8 March 2017. Retrieved 16 February 2018.
- ^ "Ludwig Wittgenstein: Background". Wittgenstein archive. University of Cambridge. Archived from the original on 18 December 2008. Retrieved 2 September 2010.
- ^ McGuinness 1988, p. 21.
- ^ P. M. S. Hacker. "Wittgenstein, Ludwig Josef Johann". mathshistory.st-andrews.ac.uk. University of Oxford. Retrieved 27 February 2021.
- ^ "Verlorenes Erbe (Wien): Die verschwundenen Wittgensteinhäuser". www.initiative-denkmalschutz.at. Verein Initiative Denkmalschutz. 24 March 2021. Retrieved 27 April 2021.
- ^ Bartley 1994, p. 16.
- ^ a b c Malcolm, Norman; Winch, Peter (1994). Wittgenstein: A Religious Point of View?. Cornell University Press. ISBN 978-1-134-72579-3.
- ^ a b Monk 1990, p. 8.
- ^ Portrait of Margaret Stonborough Wittgenstein, 1905 by Gustav Klimt
- ^ McGuinness 1988, p. 18.
- ^ Redpath, Theodore (1990). Ludwig Wittgenstein: A Student's Memoir. London: Duckworth. p. 112. ISBN 978-0-7156-2329-9.
- ^ Edmonds & Eidinow 2001, p. 157.
- ^ Monk 1990, pp. 442–443.
- ^ a b Monk 1990, pp. 14–15.
- ^ Heijerman, Eric (2005). "Three Bars by Wittgenstein" (PDF). Muzikologija (5): 393–395. doi:10.2298/MUZ0505393H. Archived (PDF) from the original on 14 July 2014.
- ^ a b Monk 1990, p. 11.
- ^ Kenny, Anthony (30 December 1990). "Give Him Genius or Give Him Death". The New York Times.
- ^ "Ludwig Wittgenstein: Background". Wittgenstein archive. University of Cambridge. Retrieved 7 September 2010.
- ^ Fitzgerald, Michael (2000). "Did Ludwig Wittgenstein have Asperger's syndrome?". European Child & Adolescent Psychiatry. 9 (1): 61–65. doi:10.1007/s007870050117. PMID 10795857. S2CID 1015505.
- ^ Waugh 2008, p. 38.
- ^ Waugh 2008, p. 10.
- ^ Waugh 2008, pp. 24–26.
- ^ Monk 1990, p. 11ff.
- ^ Monk 1990, p. 585: "Wittgenstein was uneasy, not about homosexuality, but about sexuality itself. Love, whether of a man or a woman, was something he treasured. He regarded it as a gift, almost as a divine gift. But, together with Weininger (whose Sex and Character spells out, I believe, many attitudes towards love and sex that are implicit in much that Wittgenstein said, wrote and did), he sharply differentiated love from sex. Sexual arousal, both homo- and heterosexual, troubled him enormously. He seemed to regard it as incompatible with the sort of person he wanted to be. What the coded remarks also reveal is the extraordinary extent to which Wittgenstein's love life and his sexual life went on only in his imagination." Monk 1990, p. 583: "In the coded remarks Wittgenstein does discuss his love for, first David Pinsent, then Francis Skinner, and finally Ben Richards (this is over a period of some thirty years or so), and in that sense they do 'corroborate' his homosexuality."
- ^ Waugh 2008, pp. 22–23.
- ^ Hirschfield, Magnus (1904). Jahrbuch für sexuelle Zwischenstufen. Vol. VI. p. 724., citing an unnamed Berlin newspaper, cited in turn by Bartley, p. 36.
- ^ Waugh, Alexander (30 August 2008). "The Wittgensteins: Viennese whirl". The Daily Telegraph. Archived from the original on 11 January 2022.
- ^ Waugh 2008, p. 128.
- ^ McGuinness 1988, p. 156.
- ^ a b McGuinness 1988, pp. 51ff.
- ^ Waugh 2008, p. 33.
- ^ a b c d McGuinness 1988, p. 51.
- ^ Sandgruber, Roman (26 February 2011). "Das Geld der Wittgenstein". Oberösterreichische Nachrichten. Linz. Retrieved 5 July 2016.
- ^ a b c Hamann 2000, pp. 15–16, 79.
- ^ Stonborough-Wittgenstein, Gretl. Reviewed in "Portraits of Wittgenstein", Flowers & Ground.[full citation needed]
- ^ a b Monk 1990, p. 18.
- ^ Malcolm 1958, p. 6.
- ^ Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1980). Culture and Value. Translated by Winch, Peter. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-90435-1.
- ^ Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1980). Culture and Value. Translated by Winch, Peter. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-90435-1.
- ^ McGuinness 2008, p. 34.
- ^ Portraits of Wittgenstein, 113
- ^ Wittgenstein, Ludwig, reviewed in Wittgenstein's Religious Point of View, Tim Labron
- ^ Ashford, Bruce R. (June 2007). "Wittgenstein's Theologians: A Survey of Ludwig Wittgenstein's Impact on Theology" (PDF). Journal of the Evangelical Theological Society. 50 (2): 357–75.
- ^ Monk, Ray (20 July 1999). "Wittgenstein's Forgotten Lesson". Prospect Magazine. Retrieved 24 August 2014.
- ^ a b Monk 1990, p. 148.
- ^ a b Monk 1990, p. 136.
- ^ Monk 1990, p. 138.
- ^ Monk 1990, p. 122.
- ^ Ludwig Wittgenstein, "Lectures on Religious Belief"
- ^ a b Rush Rhees, "Ludwig Wittgenstein: Personal Recollections"
- ^ Monk 1990, pp. 19–26.
- ^ Hamann 2000, p. 229.
- ^ Cohen, M. (2008). Philosophical Tales. Blackwell. p. 216.
- ^ a b McGuinness 2008, p. 141.
- ^ Strathern, Paul (1996). Wittgenstein in 90 Minutes. Ivan R. Dee. pp. 49–50.
- ^ Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1998). Culture and Value. Translated by Finch, Peter (2nd ed.). Oxford: Blackwell. pp. 15e–19e [16e]. ISBN 978-0-631-20570-8.
- ^ Klagge 2001, pp. 221, 237.
- ^ Goldstein 1999, pp. 167ff.
- ^ "Clear and Queering Thinking". Mind. Oxford University Press. 2001. JSTOR 2659846.
- ^ McGinn, Marie (26 May 2000). "Hi Ludwig". Times Literary Supplement.
- ^ Fitzgerald, Michael (2 August 2004). Autism and creativity: Is there a link between autism in men and exceptional ability?. Routledge. p. 308. ISBN 978-1-135-45340-4.
- ^ Kersaw, Ian (2000). "Hitler, 1889–1936". W. W. Norton & Company. p. 16ff. ISBN 978-0-393-32035-0.
- ^ Monk 1990, p. 15.
- ^ Hamann 2000, p. [page needed].
- ^ a b Thiede, Roger (16 March 1998). "Phantom Wittgenstein". Focus. Archived from the original on 14 July 2021. Retrieved 7 April 2020.
- ^ Blum, Michael. "Dear reader". blumology.net. Retrieved 9 September 2010.
- ^ "Monument to the birth of the 20th century". blumology.net. Retrieved 9 September 2010.
- ^ For examples, see:
- Cornish, Kimberley (1999). The Jew of Linz. Arrow.
- Blum, Michael (2005). Monument to the birth of the 20th century [a campaign, an exhibition, a book] (in German). Translated by Margarethe Clausen. Frankfurt am Main: Revolver, Archiv für Aktuelle Kunst. ISBN 978-3-86588-047-5. OCLC 723264682.[f]
- Gibbons, Luke (29 November 2008). "An extraordinary family saga". Irish Times. Archived from the original on 22 October 2012. Retrieved 21 February 2020.
- ^ "Leonding.- Class photo with teacher Oskar Langer and Adolf Hitler as students". Das Bundesarchiv [The Federal Archives]. c. 1901. 183-R99197. Archived from the original on 18 May 2021. Retrieved 18 May 2021.
- ^ Kershaw, Ian. Hitler, 1889–1936. W. W. Norton & Company, 2000, p. 16ff.
- ^ Haidacher, Christoph; Schober, Richard (2006). Von Stadtstaaten und Imperien. Universitätsverlag Wagner. p. 140. ISBN 978-3-7030-0420-9.
- ^ Drury 1984, p. 161.
- ^ Sluga & Stern 1996, p. 2.
- ^ Sluga 2011, p. 14.
- ^ Ground, Ian. "The relentless honesty of Ludwig Wittgenstein". TLS. Retrieved 19 May 2021.
- ^ Monk 1990, p. 27.
- ^ Monk 1990, p. 29.
- ^ a b Lemco, Ian (22 January 2007). "Wittgenstein's Aeronautical Investigation". Notes and Records of the Royal Society of London. 61 (1): 39–51. doi:10.1098/rsnr.2006.0163. JSTOR 20462605. S2CID 145564093.
- ^ Monk 1990, pp. 30–35.
- ^ a b Mays 2015, p. 137.
- ^ Mays 2015, p. 138.
- ^ Beaney 1997, pp. 194–223, 258–289.
- ^ a b Monk 1990, p. 30.
- ^ a b c Monk 1990, p. 36.
- ^ Kanterian 2007, p. 36.
- ^ a b O'Connor, J.J.; Robertson, E.F. "Ludwig Josef Johann Wittgenstein". St Andrews University. Retrieved 2 September 2010.
- ^ McGuinness 1988, pp. 88–89.
- ^ McGuinness 1988, p. 88.
- ^ a b Monk 1990, p. 41.
- ^ Russell 1998, p. 282.
- ^ Pitt, Jack (1981). "Russell and the Cambridge Moral Sciences Club". Russell: The Journal of Bertrand Russell Studies. 1 (2). doi:10.15173/russell.v1i2.1538.
- ^ Klagge, James Carl; Nordmann, Alfred, eds. (2003). Ludwig Wittgenstein: Public and Private Occasions. Rowman & Littlefield. p. 332.
- ^ Nedo & Ranchetti 1983, p. 89.
- ^ Edmonds & Eidinow 2001, pp. 22–28.
- ^ Eidinow, John; Edmonds, David (31 March 2001). "When Ludwig met Karl ..." The Guardian.
- ^ "Wittgenstein's Poker by David Edmonds and John Eidinow". The Guardian (Guardian first book award 2001). 21 November 2001.
- ^ "Minutes of the Wittgenstein's poker meeting". University of Cambridge. Archived from the original on 29 June 2011. Retrieved 7 September 2010 – via Flickr.
- ^ a b McGuinness 1988, p. 118.
- ^ Monk 1990, p. 76.
- ^ McGuinness 2008, p. 39.
- ^ a b McGuinness 2008, p. 59.
- ^ Monk 1990, p. 75.
- ^ McGuinness 2008, p. 63.
- ^ Flowers & Ground 2015, p. 151.
- ^ a b Monk 1990, p. 85.
- ^ Monk 1990, pp. 583–586.
- ^ Monk 1990, p. 369.
- ^ Monk 1990, pp. 238–240, 258, 280–281, 294, 318–319.
- ^ Goldstein 1999, p. 179.
- ^ von Wright 1990, p. 221.
- ^ von Wright 1990, p. 230.
- ^ Monk 1990, p. 58ff.
- ^ a b von Wright 1990, p. 88.
- ^ a b Kanterian 2007, p. 40.
- ^ Monk 1990, p. 71.
- ^ a b Derbyshire, Jonathan (6 September 2019). "A place to think: Wittgenstein's Norwegian retreat opens to visitors". Financial Times. Archived from the original on 10 December 2022. Retrieved 1 August 2020.
- ^ Stewart, Jon, ed. (2009). Kierkegaard's Influence on Philosophy: German and Scandinavian Philosophy. Ashgate Publishing. p. 216.
- ^ McGuinness 2008, p. 58.
- ^ Monk 1990, p. 96.
- ^ Wittgenstein 1922, p. 98.
- ^ Monk 1990, p. 262.
- ^ a b Edmonds & Eidinow 2001, pp. 45–46.
- ^ a b c d McGuinness, Brian (30 April 2012). Wittgenstein in Cambridge: Letters and Documents 1911 - 1951. John Wiley & Sons. pp. 73, 75. ISBN 978-1-4443-5089-0.
- ^ a b Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1974). "Letters to George Edward Moore". In von Wright, G. F. (ed.). Letters to Russell, Keynes, and Moore. assisted by B. F. McGuinness. Ithaca, N.Y. : Cornell University Press. pp. 150, 151.
- ^ Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1961). von Wright, G. H.; Anscombe, G. E. M. (eds.). Notebooks, 1914-1916. English Translation by G. E. M. Anscombe. New York,: Harper.
- ^ Monk 1990, p. 103.
- ^ McGuinness 1988, p. 200.
- ^ a b c King, Iain (17 April 2014). "THINKERS AT WAR – Wittgenstein". Military History Monthly. Retrieved 23 July 2014.
- ^ a b Greenstreet, Stuart. "Wittgenstein, Tolstoy and the Folly of Logical Positivism". Philosophy Now. Retrieved 23 July 2014.
- ^ Monk 1990, pp. 137–142.
- ^ Waugh 2008, p. 114.
- ^ Monk 1990, p. 137.
- ^ Monk 1990, p. 154.
- ^ Klagge, James Carl (22 December 2010). Wittgenstein in Exile. MIT Press. p. 68. ISBN 978-0-262-01534-9.
- ^ Monk 1990, p. 141.
- ^ Monk 1990, pp. 141–142.
- ^ Monk 1990, pp. 44, 116, 382–384.
- ^ Schardt, Bill; Large, David. "Wittgenstein, Tolstoy, and the Gospel in Brief". The Philosopher. 89 (1).
- ^ Tolstoy, Leo (1896). The Gospel in Brief. New York: T.Y. Crowell. pp. 2, 17–100. ISBN 978-1-152-21927-4.
- ^ Hanna, Robert. "Kant, Wittgenstein, and Transcendental Philosophy" (PDF). Archived from the original (PDF) on 23 May 2013.
- ^ King, Iain (17 April 2014). "Thinker at War". Retrieved 23 July 2014.
... the two halves of his war service seem to be reflected in a change of writing style. Protected from danger until spring 1916, his words were dry, abstract, and logical. Only when he was in the midst of action did he confront ethics and aesthetics, concluding their 'truths' could only be shown, not stated.
- ^ Monk 1990, p. 183.
- ^ a b Bartley 1994, pp. 33–39, 45.
- ^ Bartley 1994, pp. 33–34.
- ^ "Death of D.H. Pinsent: Recovery of the Body". Birmingham Daily Mail. 15 May 1918. Retrieved 7 September 2010 – via Mike Johnston (3 August 2009). "Wittgenstein in Birmingham". Eyes v. Ears.
The body of Mr. David Hugh Pinsent, a civilian observer, son of Mr. and Mrs. Hume Pinsent, of Foxcombe Hill, near Oxford and Birmingham, the second victim of last Wednesday's aeroplane accident in West Surrey, was last night found in the Basingstoke Canal, at Frimley.
- ^ Monk 1990, p. 169.
- ^ Edmonds & Eidinow 2001, p. 68.
- ^ Waugh 2008, p. 150.
- ^ Klagge 2001, p. 185.
- ^ Malcolm, Norman (19 November 1981). "Wittgenstein's Confessions". London Review of Books. Vol. 3, no. 21.
- ^ Monk 1990, p. 195.
- ^ Bartley 1994, p. 107.
- ^ Monk 1990, pp. 196, 198.
- ^ Russell 1922.
- ^ Russell, Nieli (1987). Wittgenstein: From Mysticism to Ordinary Language. SUNY Press. p. 113. ISBN 978-1-4384-1471-3.
- ^ Edmonds & Eidinow 2001, pp. 35ff.
- ^ a b "Ludwig Wittgenstein: Tractatus and Teaching". Cambridge Wittgenstein archive. Archived from the original on 13 February 2010. Retrieved 4 September 2010.
- ^ White, Roger (2006). Wittgenstein's Tractatus logico-philosophicus. Continuum International Publishing Group. p. 145.
- ^ Grayling, A. C. (2001). Wittgenstein: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford University Press. p. 16ff. ISBN 978-0-19-285411-7.
- ^ Tractatus (Ogden translation), preface.
- ^ Monk 1990, p. 207.
- ^ The English is from the original Ogden/Ramsey translation.
- ^ Monk 1990, pp. 212, 214–216, 220–221..
- ^ Mellor, D.H. (1995). "Cambridge Philosophers I: F.P. Ramsey". Philosophy. 70 (272): 243–26299. doi:10.1017/S0031819100065396. S2CID 143786971.
- ^ a b c Monk 1990, p. 212.
- ^ Ezard, John (19 February 2005). "Philosopher's rare 'other book' goes on sale". The Guardian.
- ^ "Translating Wittgenstein: into English, for artists, to speak now – A Conversation with Bettina Funcke and Paul Chan". Printed Matter. Retrieved 4 December 2020.
- ^ a b Dollinger, Stefan (2023). "Who is afraid of pluricentricity?". In Marcus Callies; Stefanie Hehner (eds.). Pluricentric Languages and Language Education: Pedagogical Implications and Innovative Approaches to Language Teaching. Translated by Dollinger, Stefan. Abingdon: Routledge. p. 218.
- ^ Monk 1990, pp. 224, 232–233.
- ^ a b Monk 1990, p. 225.
- ^ Waugh 2008, p. 162.
- ^ Monk 1990, p. 232.
- ^ Monk 1990, pp. 370–371.
- ^ Hanfling, Oswald (1981). Essential Readings in Logical Positivism. Oxford: Blackwell. p. 3. ISBN 978-0-631-12566-2.
- ^ Grayling, A. C. (22 February 2001). Wittgenstein: a very short introduction. Oxford. pp. 65–72. ISBN 0-19-285411-9. OCLC 46909597.
{{cite book}}
: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link) - ^ "The Limits of Science – and Scientists – The Crux". 7 September 2012. Archived from the original on 30 June 2017. Retrieved 16 February 2018.
- ^ Rudolf Carnap (1963). "Autobiography". In P.A. Schilpp (ed.). The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap. The Library of Living Philosophers, Volume 11. La Salle: Open Court. pp. 25–27.
- ^ a b Hyde, Lewis (6 April 2008). "Making It". The New York Times.
- ^ a b Jeffries, Stuart (5 January 2002). "A dwelling for the gods". The Guardian.
- ^ a b Monk 1990, p. 240.
- ^ Monk 1990, p. 255.
- ^ Alan Wood (1957). Bertrand Russell: The Passionate Sceptic. (London: Allen and Unwin). p. 156
- ^ Monk 1990, p. 271.
- ^ Braithwaite 1970, p. [page needed].
- ^ "Ludwig Wittgenstein: Return to Cambridge". Cambridge Wittgenstein Archive. Archived from the original on 3 November 2007.
- ^ "MacTutor: Biography of Éamon de Valera".
The most important contribution de Valera made to mathematics both in Ireland and internationally was the foundation of the Dublin Institute for Advanced Studies (DIAS) in 1940.
- ^ Waugh 2008, pp. 137ff, 204–209.
- ^ Waugh 2008, pp. 224–226.
- ^ Klagge 2001, p. 221.
- ^ Edmonds & Eidinow 2001, pp. 98, 105.
- ^ "No. 34622". The London Gazette (Supplement). 5 May 1939. p. 2994.
- ^ Edmonds & Eidinow 2001, p. 98.
- ^ Malcolm 1958, pp. 23–24.
- ^ Malcolm 1958, p. 25.
- ^ Monk 1990, p. 528.
- ^ Hoffmann, Josef (October 2003). "Hard-boiled Wit: Ludwig Wittgenstein and Norbert Davis". CADS.
- ^ Malcolm 1958, p. 26.
- ^ Hodges, Andrew (2014). Alan Turing: The Enigma. London: Vintage. p. 194. ISBN 978-1-78470-008-9.
- ^ Diamond 1989.
- ^ Another young mathematician with memories of an eccentric Wittgenstein was Freeman Dyson: "He invited me into his rooms one day ... I was thrilled. ... So I came in there, and there was one chair, and he invited me to sit down in it. It was a canvass deckchair, which meant I was practically lying horizontally ... and he was standing uncomfortably, waiting for me to say something. I found it acutely embarrassing, but ... I'd come in and so I thought I might as well try. And so eventually ... I said to him, 'Well, you know, I read the Tractatus. I'd be interested to know whether you still believe the things you said in the Tractatus, or have you changed your mind?' So Wittgenstein looked at me – very, very hostile fashion – 'Tell me, please: which newspaper do you represent?' That was the end of the conversation. There was another long silence, then I drank the coffee and left." "Freeman Dyson: Coming to Cambridge as a Fellow – Wittgenstein". Web of Stories. YouTube. 21 September 2016. Event occurs at 1:20. Retrieved 25 November 2023.
- ^ Lambridis, Helle (1963). Szczesny, Gerhard (ed.). "Erdachtes Gespräch mit Wittgenstein". Club Voltaire: Jahrbuch für kritische Aufklärung. 1. Munich: Szczesny Verlag: 257–270.
- ^ Lambridis, Helle (2004). Φανταστικός διάλογος με τον Wittgenstein [Imagined Dialogue with Wittgenstein]. Athens: Academy of Athens. ISBN 960-404-052-9.
- ^ a b Monk 1990, p. 431.
- ^ Monk 1990, p. 434.
- ^ Monk 1990, p. 432.
- ^ Monk 1990, p. 436.
- ^ Monk 1990, p. 443.
- ^ Monk 1990, pp. 442–423.
- ^ a b Schardt, Bill. "Wittgenstein upon Tyne". Newcastle Philosophical Society. Archived from the original on 6 September 2019. Retrieved 8 April 2020.
- ^ Cain, MJ. "Wittgenstein's Significance". Philosophy Now (33).
- ^ Stewart, G.J. (2007). "Wittgenstein and the concept of "wound shock"". ANZ Journal of Surgery. 77 (s1): A82 – A83. doi:10.1111/j.1445-2197.2007.04130_6.x. S2CID 73370285.
- ^ Monk 1990, p. 447.
- ^ Kinlen, Leo. "Wittgenstein in Newcastle". In Flowers & Ground (2018), p. 364.
- ^ a b "Not just any old rubbish". Evening Chronicle.
- ^ Cook, G.C. (2006). "Erasmus Darwin Barlow". British Medical Journal. 332 (7544): 798. PMC 1420686.
- ^ a b Monk 1990, p. 493.
- ^ Monk 1990, p. 496.
- ^ a b c "Ludwig Wittgenstein: Final Years". Cambridge Wittgenstein archive. Archived from the original on 5 March 2009. Retrieved 8 September 2010.
- ^ Hayes, John (2018). "Wittgenstein's Irish Cottage". History Ireland. 26 (4): 36–38. ISSN 0791-8224. JSTOR 26565897.
For four months during that time he stayed in a cottage in Rosroe, Co. Galway, a dispersed settlement of six houses set between the mouth of Killary Harbour and a sea inlet called 'Little Killary'. 'Quay House', on the village pier, was owned by Myles Drury (1904–87), elder brother of a former Wittgenstein student, Maurice O'Connor Drury (1907–76).
- ^ Malcolm 2001, p. [page needed].
- ^ a b Malcolm 1958, p. 79ff.
- ^ a b Malcolm 1958, pp. 80–81.
- ^ Roy, Louis (8 January 2016). "On Anscombe and Wittgenstein". Dominican University College. Archived from the original on 17 May 2021. Retrieved 26 July 2019.
- ^ A Guide to Churchill College, Cambridge: text by Mark Goldie (2009), pages 62–63
- ^ Monk 1990, pp. 576–580.
- ^ "RESTORATION". British Wittgenstein Society. Archived from the original on 16 April 2024. Retrieved 2 May 2024.
- ^ Malcolm 2001, pp. 59–60.
- ^ Labron, Tim (2006). Wittgenstein's Religious Point of View. Continuum International Publishing Group. p. 47. ISBN 978-0-8264-9027-8.
- ^ Child, William (2011). Wittgenstein. Taylor & Francis. p. 218. ISBN 978-1-136-73137-2.
- ^ Kanterian 2007, pp. 145–146.
- ^ Drury 1984, p. 160; cf. Drury 1973, pp. ix, xiv.
- ^ PI, § 38.
- ^ PI, § 107.
- ^ PI, § 133.
- ^ Stern 2010.
- ^ "Wittgenstein's Nachlass". wab.uib.no. Retrieved 10 November 2022.
- ^ "Unpublished Wittgenstein Archive explored" (Press release). Cambridge University. 28 April 2011.
- ^ "The case full of new Wittgenstein". The Times. ISSN 0140-0460. Retrieved 17 October 2020.
- ^ Malcolm, Norman (1984). Ludwig Wittgenstein: A Memoir (2nd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press. p. 12. ISBN 978-0-19-924759-2. (p. 13 in the first edition)
- ^ Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1969). On Certainty. New York: Harper & Row. p. vie. ISBN 978-0-06-131686-9.
- ^ Lackey, Douglas (December 1999). "What are the modern classics? The Baruch Poll of Great Philosophy in the Twentieth Century". Philosophical Forum. 30 (4): 329–346. doi:10.1111/0031-806X.00022.
- ^ "What are the Modern Classics?". lindenbranch.weblogs.us. Archived from the original on 20 August 2011. Retrieved 3 September 2010.
- ^ "The one hundred most influential works in cognitive science in the 20th century". Millennium Project. Archived from the original on 11 October 2011.
- ^ Richter, Duncan J. "Ludwig Wittgenstein (1889–1951)". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 16 February 2022.
- ^ "Peter Hacker". Philosophy Now. Retrieved 17 October 2013.
- ^ Biletzki, Anat; Matar, Anat (2 May 2018) [First published Fri Nov 8, 2002]. "Ludwig Wittgenstein". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 17 May 2021.
- ^ Bunge, Mario (2020). "Mario Bunge nos dijo: "Se puede ignorar la filosofía, pero no evitarla"" [Mario Bunge told us: "Philosophy can be ignored, but it cannot be avoided"] (in Spanish). Filosofía&Co.
- ^ Bunge, Mario (2010). "10". Philosophy in Crisis: The Need for Reconstruction. New York: Prometheus Books.
- ^ Bunge, Mario (1999). Social Science Under Debate: A Philosophical Perspective. Toronto: University of Toronto Press. p. 57.
- ^ Bunge, Mario; Ardila, Rubén (1987). Philosophy of Psychology. New York: Springer-Verlag. p. 11.
- ^ Malcolm 1958, pp. 1–2.
- ^ a b c Glock, Hans-Johann (2007). "Perspectives on Wittgenstein: An intermittently opinionated survey". In Kahane, Guy; Kanterian, Edward; Kuusela, Oskari (eds.). Wittgenstein and his interpreters: Essays in memory of Gordon Baker. Blackwell. pp. 37–65. ISBN 978-1-4051-2922-0.
- ^ Crary & Reed 2000, p. 1.
- ^ Wisdom, John (1953). Philosophy and Psycho-Analysis. Blackwell.
- ^ Bouwsma, O.K. (16 March 1961). "The Blue Book". The Journal of Philosophy. 58 (6): 141–162. doi:10.2307/2023409. JSTOR 2023409.
- ^ Read, Rupert (2020). Wittgenstein's Liberatory Philosophy: Thinking Through His Philosophical Investigations. doi:10.4324/9781003090977. ISBN 978-1-00-309097-7. S2CID 224868256.
- ^ "WPTC #2 – Sluga: Wittgenstein as a Liberatory Thinker". YouTube. 5 June 2020.
- ^ "Rupert Read and Hans Sluga on Wittgenstein's Liberatory Philosophy". YouTube. 26 April 2021.
- ^ Monk 1990, p. 471.
- ^ Russell, Bertrand (1959). My Philosophical Development. New York: Allen & Unwin. pp. 216–217. ISBN 978-0-04-192015-4.
- ^ Kripke 1982, p. 60.
- ^ McGinn, Colin (1984). Wittgenstein on Meaning: An Interpretation and Evaluation. Basil Blackwell.
Sources
[edit]- Bartley, William Warren (1994) [1973]. Wittgenstein. Open Court. ISBN 978-0-397-00751-6.
- Beaney, Michael, ed. (1997). The Frege Reader. Blackwell.
- Braithwaite, R. B. (1970). "George Edward Moore, 1873–1958". In Alice Ambrose; Morris Lazerowitz (eds.). G.E. Moore: Essays in Retrospect. Allen & Unwin.
- Crary, Alice; Reed, Rupert (2000). The New Wittgenstein. Routledge.
- Diamond, Cora, ed. (1989). Wittgenstein's Lectures on the Foundations of Mathematics. University Of Chicago Press.
- Drury, Maurice O'Connor (1973). The Danger of Words and Writings on Wittgenstein. Routledge and Kegan Paul.
- Drury, Maurice O'Connor (1984). "Conversations with Wittgenstein". In Rhees, Rush (ed.). Recollections of Wittgenstein. New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-287628-7.
- Edmonds, David; Eidinow, John (2001). Wittgenstein's Poker. Ecco.
- Flowers, F.A. III; Ground, Ian (2015). Portraits of Wittgenstein, Volume 1. Bloomsbury Academic. ISBN 978-1-4725-8978-1.
- Flowers, F.A. III; Ground, Ian (2018). Portraits of Wittgenstein (Abridged ed.). Bloomsbury Academic. ISBN 978-1-350-04663-4.
- Goldstein, Laurence (1999). Clear and Queer Thinking: Wittgenstein's Development and his Relevance to Modern Thought. Rowman & Littlefield. ISBN 978-0-8476-9546-1.
- Hamann, Brigitte (2000). Hitler's Vienna: A Dictator's Apprenticeship. Translated by Thornton, Thomas. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-514053-8.
- Kanterian, Edward (2007). Ludwig Wittgenstein. Reaktion Books. ISBN 978-1-86189-320-8.
- Kenny, Anthony (1984). The Legacy of Wittgenstein. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. ISBN 978-0-6311-5063-3.
- Klagge, James Carl, ed. (2001). Wittgenstein: Biography and Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-00868-6.
- Kripke, Saul (1982). Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language. Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-95401-4.
- Malcolm, Norman (1958). Ludwig Wittgenstein: A Memoir. Oxford University Press.
- Malcolm, Norman (2001). Ludwig Wittgenstein: A Memoir (2nd ed.). Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-924759-2.
- Mays, Wolfe. "Wittgenstein in Cambridge". In Flowers & Ground (2015).
- McGuinness, Brian (1988). Wittgenstein: A Life: Young Ludwig 1889–1921. University of California Press. ISBN 978-0-520-06496-6. pp. 51ff
- McGuinness, Brian (2008). Wittgenstein in Cambridge: Letters and Documents 1911–1951. Wiley-Blackwell.
- Monk, Ray (1990). Ludwig Wittgenstein: The Duty of Genius. Free Press. ISBN 978-1-4481-1267-8.
- Monk, Ray (2005). How to Read Wittgenstein. W.W. Norton & Company. ISBN 978-1-86207-724-9.
- Nedo, Michael; Ranchetti, Michele, eds. (1983). Ludwig Wittgenstein: sein Leben in Bildern und Texten. Suhrkamp. ISBN 978-3-518-04673-9.
- Russell, Bertrand. Introduction. In Wittgenstein (1922), pp. 7-23.
- Russell, Bertrand (1998). Autobiography. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-18985-9.
- Sluga, Hans (2011). Wittgenstein. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. ISBN 978-1-4443-4329-8.
- Sluga, Hans; Stern, David G. (1996). The Cambridge Companion to Wittgenstein. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-46591-5.
- Stern, David (September 2010). "The Bergen Electronic Edition of Wittgenstein's Nachlass". European Journal of Philosophy. 18 (3): 455–467. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0378.2010.00425.x.
- von Wright, Georg Henrik, ed. (1990). A Portrait of Wittgenstein as a Young Man: From the Diary of David Hume Pinsent 1912–1914. Blackwell. ISBN 978-0-631-17511-7.
- Waugh, Alexander (2008). The House of Wittgenstein: A Family at War. Random House of Canada. ISBN 978-1-4088-4202-7.
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1922). Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Kegan Paul. Original German and C. K. Ogden's English translation side by side.
Further reading
[edit]Bergen and Cambridge archives
[edit]- Wittgenstein Archives at the University of Bergen Archived 24 July 2011 at the Wayback Machine. Retrieved 16 September 2010.
- Wittgenstein News, University of Bergen. Retrieved 16 September 2010.
- Wittgenstein Source, University of Bergen. Retrieved 16 September 2010.
- The Cambridge Wittgenstein Archive. Retrieved 16 September 2010.
Papers about his Nachlass
[edit]- Stern, David (September 2010). "The Bergen Electronic Edition of Wittgenstein's Nachlass". European Journal of Philosophy. 18 (3): 455–467. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0378.2010.00425.x. ISSN 1468-0378. Via HAL archives-ouvertes.fr Via zenodo
- Von Wright, G.H. "The Wittgenstein Papers", The Philosophical Review. 78, 1969.
Other
[edit]- Agassi, J. Ludwig Wittgenstein's Philosophical Investigations: An Attempt at a Critical Rationalist Appraisal. Cham: Springer, 2018, Synthese Library, vol. 401.
- Arnswald, Ulrich (2024). "A Test of Fire of One's Character": Ludwig Wittgenstein's Self-Examination by Means of War in World War I". Journal of Austrian Studies. 57 (2): 65–86. doi:10.1353/oas.2024.a929388.
- Arnswald, Ulrich (2009). In Search of Meaning: Ludwig Wittgenstein on Ethics, Mysticism and Religion. Universitätsverlag Karlsruhe. ISBN 978-3-866442-18-4.
- Baker, G.P. and Hacker, P. M. S. Wittgenstein: Understanding and Meaning. Blackwell, 1980.
- Baker, G.P. and Hacker, P. M. S. Wittgenstein: Rules, Grammar, and Necessity. Blackwell, 1985.
- Baker, G.P. and Hacker, P. M. S. Wittgenstein: Meaning and Mind. Blackwell, 1990.
- Baker, Gordon P., and Katherine J. Morris. Wittgenstein's Method: Neglected Aspects: Essays on Wittgenstein. Malden, MA: Blackwell, 2004.
- Barrett, Cyril (1991). Wittgenstein on Ethics and Religious Belief. Blackwell.
- Brockhaus, Richard R. Pulling Up the Ladder: The Metaphysical Roots of Wittgenstein's Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Open Court, 1990.
- Conant, James F. "Putting Two and Two Together: Kierkegaard, Wittgenstein, and the Point of View for Their Work as Authors" in The Grammar of Religious Belief, edited by D.Z. Phillips. St. Martins Press, NY: 1996
- Crary, Alice (2007). Wittgenstein and the Moral Life: Essays in Honor of Cora Diamond. MIT Press. ISBN 978-0-262-53286-0.
- Crary, Alice (2018). "Wittgenstein goes to Frankfurt (and finds something useful to say)". Nordic Wittgenstein Review. 7 (1): 7–41.
- Creegan, Charles (1989). Wittgenstein and Kierkegaard: Religion, Individuality and Philosophical Method. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-00066-6.
- Eagleton, Terry (15 May 2022). "Ludwig Wittgenstein's war on philosophy". UnHerd. Retrieved 23 May 2022.
- Edwards, James C. (1982). Ethics Without Philosophy: Wittgenstein and the Moral Life. University Presses of Florida.
- Engelmann, Paul. Letters from Ludwig Wittgenstein With a Memoir. Blackwell, 1967; New York: Horizon Press, 1968. The memoir is reprinted in F. A. Flowers III and Ian Ground, eds., Portraits of Wittgenstein, ch. 20 (2015) [1999], and Portraits of Wittgenstein: Abridged Edition, ch. 13 (2018). Bloomsbury Academic.
- Fraser, Giles (25 January 2010). "Investigating Wittgenstein, part 1: Falling in love". The Guardian.
- Gellner, Ernest (1979) [1959]. Words and Things. Routledge & Kegan Paul.
- Grayling, A. C. (2001). Wittgenstein: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-285411-7.
- Hacker, P. M. S. Insight and Illusion: Themes in the Philosophy of Wittgenstein. Clarendon Press, 1986.
- Hacker, P. M. S. "Wittgenstein, Ludwig Josef Johann", in Ted Honderich (ed.). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press, 1995.
- Hacker, P. M. S. Wittgenstein's Place in Twentieth Century Analytic Philosophy. Blackwell, 1996.
- Hacker, P. M. S. Wittgenstein: Mind and Will. Blackwell, 1996.
- Holt, Jim, "Positive Thinking" (review of Karl Sigmund, Exact Thinking in Demented Times: The Vienna Circle and the Epic Quest for the Foundations of Science, Basic Books, 449 pp.), The New York Review of Books, vol. LXIV, no. 20 (21 December 2017), pp. 74–76.
- Jareño-Alarcón, Joaquín. Ludwig Wittgenstein: The Meaning of Life. Wiley-Blackwell, 2023.
- Jormakka, Kari. "The Fifth Wittgenstein", Datutop 24, 2004, a discussion of the connection between Wittgenstein's architecture and his philosophy.
- Kishik, David (2008). Wittgenstein's Form of Life. Continuum.
- Klagge, James C. Wittgenstein's Artillery: Philosophy as Poetry. Cambridge, Massachusetts: The MIT Press, 2021.
- Klagge, James C. Simply Wittgenstein. New York: Simply Charly, 2016.
- Klagge, James C. Wittgenstein in Exile. Cambridge, Massachusetts: The MIT Press, 2011.
- Leitner, Bernhard (1973). The Architecture of Ludwig Wittgenstein: A Documentation. Press of the Nova Scotia College of Art and Design.
- Levy, Paul. Moore: G.E. Moore and the Cambridge Apostles. Weidenfeld & Nicolson, 1979.
- Luchte, James. "Under the Aspect of Time ("sub specie temporis"): Heidegger, Wittgenstein, and the Place of the Nothing", Philosophy Today, Volume 53, Number 2 (Spring, 2009)
- Lurie, Yuval. Wittgenstein on the Human Spirit.. Rodopi, 2012.
- Macarthur, David. "Working on Oneself in Philosophy and Architecture: A Perfectionist Reading of the Wittgenstein House". Architectural Theory Review, vol. 19, no. 2 (2014): 124–140.
- Padilla Gálvez, Jesús, ed. Wittgenstein, from a New Point of View. Frankfurt am Main: Lang, 2003. ISBN 3-631-50623-6.
- Padilla Gálvez, Jesús, ed. Philosophical Anthropology. Wittgenstein's Perspectives. Berlin, Germany: Ontos Verlag, 2010. ISBN 978-3-86838-067-5.
- Pears, David F. "A Special Supplement: The Development of Wittgenstein's Philosophy", The New York Review of Books, 10 July 1969.
- Pears, David F. The False Prison: A Study of the Development of Wittgenstein's Philosophy, Volumes 1 and 2. Oxford University Press, 1987 and 1988.
- Perloff, Marjorie (1996). Wittgenstein's Ladder: Poetic Language and the Strangeness of the Ordinary. University of Chicago Press.
- Perloff, Marjorie (2016). "Becoming a 'Different' Person: Wittgenstein's 'Gospels'", in Perloff, Marjorie, Edge of Irony: Modernism in the Shadow of the Habsburg Empire. Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press.
- Peterman, James F. (1992). Philosophy as Therapy. SUNY Press.
- Pitcher, George. The Philosophy of Wittgenstein. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, Inc., 1964.
- Richter, Duncan J. "Ludwig Wittgenstein (1889–1951)", Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 30 August 2004. Retrieved 16 September 2010.
- Rizzo, Francesco, "Kauffman lettore di Wittgenstein", Università degli studi di Palermo, Palermo, 2017.
- Scheman, Naomi and O'Connor, Peg (eds.). Feminist Interpretations of Ludwig Wittgenstein. Penn State Press, 2002.
- Schönbaumsfeld, Genia. A Confusion of the Spheres: Kierkegaard and Wittgenstein on Philosophy and Religion. Oxford University Press, 2007.
- Shanker, S.; Shanker, V. A. (1986). Ludwig Wittgenstein: Critical Assessments. Croom Helm.
- Shyam Wuppuluri, N. C. A. da Costa (eds.). "Wittgensteinian (adj.): Looking at the World from the Viewpoint of Wittgenstein's Philosophy" Springer – The Frontiers Collection, 2019. Foreword by A. C. Grayling.
- Temelini, Michael. Wittgenstein and the Study of Politics. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2015.
- Wallgren, Thomas H., ed. (2024). The Creation of Wittgenstein: Understanding the Roles of Rush Rhees, Elizabeth Anscombe and Georg Henrik von Wright. Bloomsbury Publishing.
- Whitehead, Alfred North; Russell, Bertrand (1910). Principia Mathematica. Cambridge University Press.
- Xanthos, Nicolas, "Wittgenstein's Language Games", in Louis Hebert (dir.), Signo (online), Rimouski (Quebec, Canada), 2006.
Works referencing Wittgenstein
[edit]- Doctorow, E. L. City of God. Plume, 2001, depicts an imaginary rivalry between Wittgenstein and Einstein.
- Doxiadis, Apostolos and Papadimitriou, Christos. Logicomix. Bloomsbury, 2009.
- Duffy, Bruce. The World as I Found It. Ticknor & Fields, 1987, a fictionalized account of Wittgenstein's life.
- Jarman, Derek. Wittgenstein, a biopic of Wittgenstein with a script by Terry Eagleton, British Film Institute, 1993.
- Kerr, Philip. A Philosophical Investigation, Chatto & Windus, 1992, a dystopian thriller set in 2012.
- Markson, David. Wittgenstein's Mistress. Dalkey Archive Press, 1988, an experimental novel, a first-person account of what it would be like to live in the world of the Tractatus.
- Murdoch, Iris. Nuns and Soldiers. The first line of the novel is "'WITTGENSTEIN —'". London: Chatto & Windus, 1980.
- Tully, James. Strange Multiplicity: Constitutionalism in an Age of Diversity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995
- Wallace, David Foster. The Broom of the System. Penguin Books, 1987, a novel.
External links
[edit]- Works by Ludwig Wittgenstein in eBook form at Standard Ebooks
- Works by Ludwig Wittgenstein at Project Gutenberg
- C.K. Ogden's English translation of Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (Gutenberg)
- Works by or about Ludwig Wittgenstein at the Internet Archive
- Works by Ludwig Wittgenstein at LibriVox (public domain audiobooks)
- Works by Ludwig Wittgenstein at The Ludwig Wittgenstein Project
- "Ludwig Wittgenstein". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- "Ludwig Wittgenstein: Later Philosophy of Mathematics". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Trinity College Chapel
- John Searle on Ludwig Wittgenstein on YouTube
- BBC Radio 4 programme on Wittgenstein, broadcast 13 December 2011
- "A. J. Ayer's Critique of Wittgenstein's Private Language Argument"
- Wittgenstein, BBC Radio 4 discussion with Ray Monk, Barry Smith & Marie McGinn (In Our Time, 4 December 2003)
- Ludwig Wittgenstein at the Mathematics Genealogy Project
- The Significance of Ontology in Epistemological Research – Hannah Arendt Memorial Lecture, 1980
- Wittgenstein's Jet BBC Radio 4 programme Broadcast Friday 2 January 2015
- GB Patent GB191027087A: Improvements in Propellers applicable for Aerial Machines, 1910 Espacenet
- Ludwig Wittgenstein at IMDb
- Steven Pinker on Concepts & Reasoning
- Ludwig Wittgenstein
- 1889 births
- 1951 deaths
- 20th-century Austrian mathematicians
- 20th-century Austrian philosophers
- 20th-century Austrian writers
- 20th-century British essayists
- 20th-century British mathematicians
- 20th-century British philosophers
- Alumni of Trinity College, Cambridge
- Analytic philosophers
- Austrian agnostics
- Austrian bisexual people
- Austrian essayists
- Austrian expatriates in Norway
- Austrian expatriates in the United Kingdom
- Austrian Jews
- Austrian LGBTQ writers
- Austrian logicians
- Austrian non-fiction writers
- Austrian people of Czech-Jewish descent
- Austrian people of German-Jewish descent
- Austrian people of Jewish descent
- Austrian people of Slovenian descent
- Austrian people with disabilities
- Austrian prisoners of war
- Austrian refugees
- Austro-Hungarian military personnel of World War I
- Bertrand Russell Professors of Philosophy
- Bisexual academics
- Bisexual Jews
- Bisexual male writers
- Bisexual military personnel
- British agnostics
- British bisexual writers
- British expatriates in Norway
- British Jews
- British logicians
- British male essayists
- British people of Austrian-Jewish descent
- British people of Czech-Jewish descent
- British people of German-Jewish descent
- British people of Slovenian descent
- British writers with disabilities
- Cambridge University Moral Sciences Club
- Deaths from prostate cancer in England
- Epistemologists
- Fellows of Trinity College, Cambridge
- Jewish agnostics
- Jewish philosophers
- LGBTQ mathematicians
- LGBTQ philosophers
- Linguistic turn
- Metaphilosophers
- Metaphysicians
- Naturalised citizens of the United Kingdom
- Ontologists
- Ordinary language philosophy
- People associated with the University of Manchester
- People with post-traumatic stress disorder
- Philosophers of art
- Philosophers of culture
- Philosophers of language
- Philosophers of logic
- Philosophers of mathematics
- Philosophers of mind
- Philosophers of social science
- Philosophy writers
- Social philosophers
- Technische Universität Berlin alumni
- Theorists on Western civilization
- Wittgenstein family
- Wittgensteinian philosophers
- World War I prisoners of war held by Italy
- Writers from Vienna